


Estude fácil! Tem muito documento disponível na Docsity
Ganhe pontos ajudando outros esrudantes ou compre um plano Premium
Prepare-se para as provas
Estude fácil! Tem muito documento disponível na Docsity
Prepare-se para as provas com trabalhos de outros alunos como você, aqui na Docsity
Os melhores documentos à venda: Trabalhos de alunos formados
Prepare-se com as videoaulas e exercícios resolvidos criados a partir da grade da sua Universidade
Responda perguntas de provas passadas e avalie sua preparação.
Ganhe pontos para baixar
Ganhe pontos ajudando outros esrudantes ou compre um plano Premium
Comunidade
Peça ajuda à comunidade e tire suas dúvidas relacionadas ao estudo
Descubra as melhores universidades em seu país de acordo com os usuários da Docsity
Guias grátis
Baixe gratuitamente nossos guias de estudo, métodos para diminuir a ansiedade, dicas de TCC preparadas pelos professores da Docsity
- - -
Tipologia: Notas de estudo
1 / 4
Esta página não é visível na pré-visualização
Não perca as partes importantes!
Brain Research Reviews 26 Ž^1998. 83–
Department of Neurology, Uni Õ ersity of Iowa College of Medicine, 200 Hawkins Dri Õ e, Iowa City, IA 52242 USA
Contents
References.......................................................................... 86
1. Neglecting emotion and missing the integrated view
It would not be possible to discuss the integrative aspects of brain function without considering the opera- tions that arise in large-scale neural systems; and it would be unreasonable not to single-out emotion among the critical integrative operations arising in that level. Yet, throughout the twentieth century, the integrated brain and mind have often been discussed with hardly any acknowl- edgment that emotion does exist, let alone that it is an important function and that understanding its neural under- pinnings is of great advantage. There are numerous reasons behind the benign neglect of emotion and I cannot mention them all and much less discuss them. In general, however, it seems fair to say that emotion must have seemed both too elusive and too subjective to attract the interest of neuroscientists or cognitive scientists concerned with re- searching that which appeared most concrete and objec- tive. It seems clear now that there is nothing more elusive about emotion than about, say, perception or memory —in fact less so, in my opinion— and it is equally clear that emotion is also no less objective. In the event, however, it did seem more elusive and less objective than other cogni- tive and behavioral phenomena. Perhaps this was so be-
) (^) Fax: q 1 Ž 319. 353-6277. (^1) Published on the World Wide Web on 27 January 1998.
cause, in post-Cartesian and especially post-Kantian ap- proaches to mind, emotion came to be regarded as the very antithesis of one good thing called reason. And who would want to spend a lifetime attempting to understand the very opposite of one good thing? Many nineteenth century creative thinkers actually did, as it turns out, and many others do again, now, but only a handful did, in between. Of those who did, one hundred and some years ago, Charles Darwin, William James, and Siegmund Freud, loom large. The neglect suffered by emotion during most of the twentieth century has some curious parallels. The first parallel is the lack of an evolutionary perspective in the study of brain and mind. By and large neuroscience and cognitive science have proceeded as if Darwin never ex- isted. The situation is now changing remarkably, in the neurosciences, and some would say that it is changing far too much and not too well within cognitive science itself. It is one thing to try to illuminate a theory by looking at a possible evolutionary account for a given phenomenon, it is another to explain current aspects of cognition in exclu- sive evolutionary terms, especially when the explanations cannot be subject to any empirical verification. The second parallel concerns the disregard for the no- tion of homeostatic regulation in the sciences of mind and brain. This does not mean, of course, that there were not numerous scientists preoccupied with understanding the neurophysiology of homeostasis; the neuroanatomy and
0165-0173r 98 r$19.00 q 1998 Elsevier Science B.V. All rights reserved.
the neurochemistry of the autonomic system; the mecha- nisms of neuroendocrine regulation; or the interrelation between nervous system and immune system. But the scientific progress made in those areas was not used to modify the prevailing views of how mind or brain worked. The importance of this point is probably best made by considering the recent exceptions to this state of affairs, for instance in the role accorded to homeostatic value in Gerald Edelman’s neural models w^ 7,8 ,x or in my own somatic marker hypothesis 4,5.^ w^ x A third parallel is the prevalent absence of a notion of organism in the sciences of mind and brain. It is not just that the mind remained linked to the brain in a rather equivocal relationship, but that the brain remained consis- tently separated from the body and thus not part of the deeply interwoven mesh of body and brain that defines a complex living organism. Again, the notion of organism was available, e.g., Goldstein w x9 ; Weiss^ w^ 11 , but it wasx rarely used. Has anything been missed by the neglect of emotion? The answer is yes, unequivocally. Let us consider the following:
well elucidated. Fortunately, the entire attitude towards emotion has begun to change. In the pages ahead I provide a brief summary of recent theoretical and factual progress in the neurobiology of emotion. Because so many new findings are being re- ported, from varied approaches, I will focus my comments on work in humans and only at the large-scale systems level.
2. Emotion and feeling
The terms emotion and feeling are usually used inter- changeably but I have suggested that they should not be. From a research perspective it is advantageous to use separate terms to designate separable components of this enchained process. The term emotion should be rightfully used to designate a collection of responses triggered from parts of the brain to the body, and from parts of the brain to other parts of the brain, using both neural and humoral routes. The end result of the collection of such responses is an emotional state , defined by changes within the body- proper, e.g., viscera, internal milieu, and within certain sectors of the brain, e.g., somatosensory cortices; neuro- transmitter nuclei in brain stem. The term feeling should be used to describe the com- plex mental state that results from the emotional state. That mental state includes: Ž .a the representation of the changes that have just occurred in the body-proper and are being signaled to body-representing structures in the cen- tral nervous system Žor have been implemented entirely in somatosensory structures via ‘as-if-body-loops’ ;^. and it also includes Ž .b a number of alterations in cognitive processing that are caused by signals secondary to brain- to-brain responses, for instance, signals from neurotrans- mitter nuclei towards varied sites in telencephalon. Both emotions and feelings are amenable to investiga- tion, all the more so if their sequential and concurrent functional components can be relatively individualized for analysis along the model suggested by the above distinc- tion. Emotion is somewhat more accessible than feeling because the triggering stimuli and sites are easier to iden- tify, and because so many of the responses are externalized and thus easier to measure. But once the neural systems which can support feelings are identified, feelings are also accessible, especially in humans, using modern neuroimag- ing tools.
3. Neural systems underlying emotion
Discussions on the neurobiology of emotion at systems level tend to revolve around the notion of limbic system, a collection of cortical and subcortical structures defined quite circularly by their very involvement in emotion. Prominent among those structures are the cingulate cortex
within and around the limbic system, circuitry connecting varied neural sites supports the operation of different emotions. For instance, work on aversive conditioning in rodents has shown that the amygdala is certainly involved in negative emotions such as fear 10,6. Work in humans,^ w^ x on the other hand, has not only confirmed the amygdala’s involvement with negative emotions such as fear and anger but also shown that the amygdala is not involved in the processing of positive emotions such as happiness, or negative emotions such as disgust. Studying patients with surgical damage to both amygdala, and with Urbach– Wiethe disease Ža condition in which total and gradual depositions of calcium leads to the circumscribed damage and functional inactivation of both amygdala , we have^. been able to show, for instance, that the recognition of facial expressions of fear and anger but not of any other emotions are selectively impaired w^ 1,2. This selective in-x volvement of the amygdala in some but not all emotions is even noticeable at non-conscious level, as shown in func- tional imaging experiments by Whalen et al. w^ 12. More-x over it is clear that some cortical structures are required for the processing of fear —for instance, the right somatosen- sory cortices— but those same structures are not needed for the processing of primitive emotions such as happiness w x3. Ongoing functional neuroimaging studies at our labora- tory demonstrate that there are varied critical sites, both within and outside the limbic system, relative to distinct emotions.
4. The rationality of emotions
Emotion is the most complex expression of homeostatic regulatory systems. The results of the emotions serve the purpose of survival even in nonminded organisms. The emotions operate along the dimensions of approach or aversion, of appetition or withdrawal. The emotions pro- tect the subject organism by avoiding predators or scaring them away, or by leading the organism to food and sex. As such, the emotions often operate as a basic mechanism for making decisions without the labors of reason, that is, without resorting to deliberated considerations of facts, options, outcomes, and rules of logic. But the emotions have other roles to play in conscious, minded, knowledge- rich organisms such as our own. In human organisms, appropriate learning can pair emotion with all manner of
facts Žfor instance, facts which describe the premises of a situation, the option taken relative to solving the problems inherent in a situation, and, perhaps most importantly, the outcomes of choosing a certain option, both immediately and in the future. The pairing of emotion and fact remains^. in memory in such a way that when the facts are consid- ered in deliberate reasoning when a similar situation is revisited, the paired emotion or some aspect of it can be reactivated. The recall allows emotion to exert its pairwise qualification effect. This can happen either as a conscious signal, e.g., a ‘gut feeling’, or as nonconscious bias, or both. In both types of action the emotions and the machin- ery underlying them play an important regulatory role in the life of an organism. This higher order role for emotion is still related to the needs of survival albeit less appar- ently. But it should be noted that beyond survival the impact of emotion in the process of reason affects the quality of survival and can help guide the creative process that best characterizes the human mind.
References
w x 1 R. Adolphs, D. Tranel, A.R. Damasio, Impaired recognition of emotion in facial expressions following bilateral damage to the human amygdala, Nature 372 Ž^1994. 669–672. w x 2 R. Adolphs, D. Tranel, H. Damasio, A.R. Damasio, Fear and the human amygdala, J. Neurosci. 15 Ž^1995. 5879–5891. w x 3 R. Adolphs, H. Damasio, D. Tranel, A.R. Damasio, Cortical systems for the recognition of emotion in facial expressions, J. Neurosci. 16 Ž 1996. 7678–7687. w x 4 A.R. Damasio, D. Tranel, H. Damasio, Somatic markers and the guidance of behavior: Theory and preliminary testing, in: H.S. Levin, H.M. Eisenberg, A.L. Benton Ž^ Eds. , Frontal Lobe Function. and Dysfunction, Oxford University Press, New York, 1991, pp. 217–229. w x 5 A.R. Damasio, Descartes’ Error: Emotion, Reason, and the Human Brain, GrossetrPutnam, New York, 1994. w x 6 M. Davis, The role of the amygdala in conditioned fear, in: J.P. Aggleton Ž Ed. , The amygdala: Neurobiological Aspects of Emotion,. Memory, and Mental Dysfunction, Wiley-Liss, New York, 1992. w x 7 G. Edelman, Neural Darwinism, Basic Books, New York, 1987. w x 8 G. Edelman, Bright Air, Brilliant Fire, Basic Books, New York,
w x 9 K. Goldstein, Aufbau des Organismus, Berlin, 1933. w 10 x J. LeDoux, The Emotional Brain: the Mysterious Underpinnings of Emotional Life, Simon and Schuster, New York, 1996. w 11 x P. Weiss, Principles of Development, Holt, New York, 1939. w 12 x P. Whalen et al., Masked presentations of emotional facial expres- sions activate the amygdala without explicit knowledge. J. Neurosci., in press.