Docsity
Docsity

Prepare for your exams
Prepare for your exams

Study with the several resources on Docsity


Earn points to download
Earn points to download

Earn points by helping other students or get them with a premium plan


Guidelines and tips
Guidelines and tips

Virtue Ethics and the Problem of Advising Fools: A Stoic Perspective, Lecture notes of Ethics

The problem of advising 'fools' or non-virtuous individuals using the principles of virtue ethics. The author argues that Stoic psychopathology offers a helpful approach to understanding how fools might approximate virtue and how advisers can guide them towards the best actions. However, the author also acknowledges the challenges in applying virtue theory to such cases and suggests that ancient Greek theorists may have a solution.

What you will learn

  • How can advisers use Socratic eudaimonism's conception of virtue to guide fools to the best action?
  • What is the problem of advising fools in the context of virtue ethics?
  • What is the difference between virtuous persons and non-virtuous persons in the context of virtue ethics?
  • What are some challenges in applying virtue theory to cases of advising fools?
  • How does Stoic psychopathology help in understanding how fools might approximate virtue?

Typology: Lecture notes

2021/2022

Uploaded on 09/27/2022

sharina
sharina 🇬🇧

4.5

(11)

217 documents

1 / 22

Toggle sidebar

This page cannot be seen from the preview

Don't miss anything!

bg1
Work in progress, for presentation at Lewis & Clark College, Nov. 2010.
Please do not quote without permission.
COMMENTS WELCOME
"VIRTUE ETHICS" AND
THE PROBLEM OF ADVISING FOOLS1
ERIC BROWN
Department of Philosophy
Washington University in St. Louis
eabrown@wustl.edu
ABSTRACT: "Virtue ethics" tells us to do what the virtuous person would do in our
circumstances. But if we are not virtuous—if we are "fools"—then the virtuous person would not
be in our circumstances. What, then, can virtue theory say to advise a fool about what to do? I
quickly suggest reasons to be pessimistic about recent approaches to this problem, and then I turn
to the ancients' eudaimonism for a fresh alternative. The ancient Socratics, including especially
the Stoics, counsel not causally promoting one's virtue or trying to follow "v-rules" but
approximating virtue. I argue that Stoic psychopathology offers considerable help in making
sense of how fools might approximate virtue and how advisers might use Socratic eudaimonism's
conception of virtue to guide fools to the best action in their circumstances.
1. The Problem of Advising Fools
Some people believe that ancient Greek and Roman philosophy provides a plausible
alternative to modern moral philosophy. Instead of thinking that one should act in accordance
with the right moral principles or that one should act so as to promote the best consequences,
these reactionaries suggest that one should act as a virtuous person would act in one's
circumstances (see, e.g., Hursthouse 1999).
But there are problems with this formula, several of which are rooted in the difference
between virtuous persons and the rest of us. First, we who are not virtuous sometimes find
1 I thank John Doris, Julia Driver, Carrie Vodehnal, and Eric Wiland for discussion of some of the ideas in this
essay, and Richard Kraut and the other participants in the May 2010 conference on ordinary virtue at
Northwestern University for their comments on an early draft.
pf3
pf4
pf5
pf8
pf9
pfa
pfd
pfe
pff
pf12
pf13
pf14
pf15
pf16

Partial preview of the text

Download Virtue Ethics and the Problem of Advising Fools: A Stoic Perspective and more Lecture notes Ethics in PDF only on Docsity!

Work in progress, for presentation at Lewis & Clark College, Nov. 2010. Please do not quote without permission. COMMENTS WELCOME

"VIRTUE ETHICS" AND

THE PROBLEM OF ADVISING FOOLS^1

ERIC BROWN

Department of Philosophy

Washington University in St. Louis

eabrown@wustl.edu

ABSTRACT: "Virtue ethics" tells us to do what the virtuous person would do in our circumstances. But if we are not virtuous—if we are "fools"—then the virtuous person would not be in our circumstances. What, then, can virtue theory say to advise a fool about what to do? I quickly suggest reasons to be pessimistic about recent approaches to this problem, and then I turn to the ancients' eudaimonism for a fresh alternative. The ancient Socratics, including especially the Stoics, counsel not causally promoting one's virtue or trying to follow "v-rules" but approximating virtue. I argue that Stoic psychopathology offers considerable help in making sense of how fools might approximate virtue and how advisers might use Socratic eudaimonism's conception of virtue to guide fools to the best action in their circumstances.

1. The Problem of Advising Fools

Some people believe that ancient Greek and Roman philosophy provides a plausible

alternative to modern moral philosophy. Instead of thinking that one should act in accordance

with the right moral principles or that one should act so as to promote the best consequences,

these reactionaries suggest that one should act as a virtuous person would act in one's

circumstances (see, e.g., Hursthouse 1999).

But there are problems with this formula, several of which are rooted in the difference

between virtuous persons and the rest of us. First, we who are not virtuous sometimes find

(^1) I thank John Doris, Julia Driver, Carrie Vodehnal, and Eric Wiland for discussion of some of the ideas in this essay, and Richard Kraut and the other participants in the May 2010 conference on ordinary virtue at Northwestern University for their comments on an early draft.

ourselves in circumstances foreign to any virtuous person. Hursthouse (1999, 50-51), for

example, imagines a cad who has led each of two women to believe that he wants to settle down

with her and has impregnated both. We cannot even begin to imagine what the virtuous person

would do in such a circumstance because a virtuous person would not be in such a circumstance.

Also, we are often unable to do what the virtuous person would do. Although the virtuous

person would dine with the presenter after the colloquium and then finish her overdue grading

after dinner, I might know that if I went to dinner, I would be unable to resist the wine that would

make me unable to work responsibly later in the evening.^2 I cannot do what the virtuous person

would do. So what should I do instead? Finally, it is clear that those of us who are not virtuous

should spend some time working toward becoming virtuous, although of course a virtuous

person does not do any such thing (cf. Railton 1986, 174n15). In each of these cases, one cannot

appeal to virtue theory's formula to explain what a person should do.

Invoking the Stoics' provocative term 'fool' to describe all who are not virtuous, I call the

problem posed by such cases the problem of advising fools.

3

The problem, thus far, is not that it

is difficult to appeal to virtue theory's general principle in order to explain what should be done,

or that it requires judgment to explain how the principle applies. The problem is that the

principle simply does not apply.

So it is tempting to revise virtue theory's general principle. Perhaps one should act as

one's virtuous counterpart would want one to act (cf. Railton 1986, 173-174) or as one's virtuous

counterpart would advise one to act (cf. Smith 1994, 151). These revisions give us a general

(^2) I seem to recall Michael Smith using an example of a hothead who thinks that he should not try to shake his victorious opponent's hand after a hard-fought tennis match, though of course his idealized counterpart would, but I cannot find the reference. I'd love some help with this. (^3) It often appears in the journals as the "problem of action-guidance" or the "practicality objection." But these labels cover a host of distinct concerns, not all of which are predicated on the gap between the virtuous and the rest of us.

difficult, or that it requires judgment, to apply the formula. It would remain difficult and require

judgment if we knew, roughly, where to look. But we do not even know that.

The problem does not entirely disappear if we give up on a single general principle and

embrace a litany of rules that express the essential commitments of virtuous dispositions.

Hursthouse (1999, 51) hopes that these "v-rules"—virtue-rules such as "try a little tenderness"

and especially vice-rules such as "don't be cruel"—would provide guidance to the cad. And of

course they might. But they might not. For how is the cad to prioritize or otherwise sort through

the various v-rules when they offer conflicting guidance? The virtuous agent was supposed to

provide a standard for this purpose, but the virtuous agent does not apply to the cad's case.

5

The

virtuous adviser applies, but without any hint of how she would sort through the v-rules. So the

many v-rules have, in a way, too much application to the fool's situation. The whole set of v-

rules, lacking any principle or model to guide our application of it, explains too many possible

actions as the best action and thereby fails to explain what a person should do.

The v-rules are an improvement over a general principle that does not apply and over a

general principle that applies without content. But I doubt that they remove the problem of

advising fools. Again, it is not merely difficult, or a matter for judgment, to get from the v-rules

to the thing to do. Without some principle or model or set of considerations to guide the

application of the v-rules, it is entirely random which of the many actions licensed or even

required by the whole set of v-rules in these particular circumstances should be done.

(^5) If I understand her right, Hursthouse (1999, 52-62) accepts (and tries to mitigate the apparent undesirability of accepting) that there are cases in which virtue theory cannot provide any guidance beyond a list of v-rules whose recommendations appear to conflict in ways that a non-virtuous person (especially an inexperienced, non-virtuous person) would be unable to sort through. Presumably, she thinks that anyone unlucky enough to be stuck in such a circumstance should seek advice from his moral superiors (35). But my question concerns this advice: how exactly does thinking about virtue help the moral superior advise the fool? Hursthouse's general principle and her v-rules do not make it clear how it could.

This is a problem for "virtue ethics." It is not necessarily fatal. Perhaps useful advice for

fools is too much to ask of a normative ethical theory. The virtue theorist's appeal to "v-rules"

puts her on equal footing with many theorists of other stripes, and they could all say that no more

applicable account of what should be done is plausible. Still, other things being equal, it would

be good for the virtue theorist to solve the problem of advising fools by offering more guidance

about how to determine what a fool should do. This is so for two reasons. First, it is entirely

plausible that, as Aristotle insisted, the point of engaging ethical theory is to live better (EN I.

1095a5-6), and plausible that ethical theorizing will not help us unless it gives useful advice to

fools.

6

Given these points' plausibility, we cannot easily believe that the problem of advising

fools is a pseudo-problem. Additionally, because, as we have seen, the problem raises nagging

questions about how best to formulate the basic principle(s) of "virtue ethics," a solution to the

problem promises to offer a better way of understanding the core commitments of "virtue

ethics."

In this essay, I suggest a potential solution to the problem by looking back. I argue that

some ancient Greek theorists of ethics have a way of understanding "virtue ethics" that solves the

problem of advising fools.

2. Eudaimonism and the Problem of Advising Fools

At first blush, it might seem obvious that the ancients offer a solution. They appeal to a

practical principle more basic than virtue theory's dictum that one should act as the virtuous

(^6) We could, I suppose, flatter ourselves with the thought that we are not fools. But it would disastrous for our theory of virtue to suppose that it is regularly attained by the likes of us, as the best responses to Doris' (2002) challenge to "virtue ethics" recognize (see esp. Kamtekar 2004). In any case, even if we were virtuous, would virtue theory then help us to live better? It seems that if virtue theory is going to help anyone at all, it needs to show the way toward virtue for people who are not virtuous.

"living well" or "doing well," and I call it Socratic because it is native to Socrates' most

prominent followers, including Plato, Aristotle, and the Stoics.

This classification of ancient eudaimonisms might raise some eyebrows,^10 but it does not

matter for my present purposes whether it is exhaustive (it is not)

11

or whether it accurately

represents Plato,

12

Aristotle,

13

or Epicurus

14

(who are, I take it, the most contentious cases).

than Humean strictures would allow) and non-causal 'for the sake of' relationships (for which, see Kraut 1989, 87 - 88, and Lear 2004). (^10) Many scholars have recognized that at least some eudaimonists think of eudaimonia as virtuous activity whereas others think of it as something separate from and produced by virtuous activity, but I do not know of any scholar (aside from Brown 2008) who has emphasized this distinction or drawn significant inferences from it. Perhaps Annas (1993, esp. 36-37) comes closest, but instead of articulating a contrast within eudaimonism, she insists that one has to abdicate eudaimonism to claim that one's final good is a state of affairs to be brought about. I believe but cannot argue here that this misconstrues Epicurean ethics, inevitably misrepresents the theory of the Protagoras (cf. Annas 1993, 37 and 228), and cannot easily accommodate later antiquity's understanding of Democritean ethics. I also depart from Annas' account by distinguishing the non- consequentialist eudaimonism according to which eudaimonia is simply virtuous activity (Socratic) from the one according to which it is virtuous activity and more (Peripatetic: see the next note). (^11) Some ancient eudaimonists saw the final good for the sake of which one should act as a grab-bag including one's action and a motley assortment of goods, some of which would be consequences of one's action. This Peripatetic view (cf. Magna Moralia 1184a25-30) became prominent in the wake of Carneades' mischievous division of ethical theories (see esp. Cicero, De Finibus V, and Stobaeus II 7.3). The view would have us consider, in addition to how we might best try to act virtuously or at least in accord with virtue, how we might best bring about the other goods that it counts as part of the eudaimonia we should bring about. Whatever insights or advantages this view might offer—and I believe that it offers more confusion and disadvantages than insights and advantages—it first needs to determine how we can best try to act virtuously or at least in accord with virtue. So the work I do in this essay might help to clarify Peripatetic eudaimonism, even though I have to leave for another occasion a fuller reckoning of the Peripatetic view. (^12) White ( citation ) thinks that Plato is not a eudaimonist at all, principally because he thinks that the Republic's philosophers sacrifice their eudaimonia to rule, but see Brown (2000 and 2004). Other scholars would question the claim that Plato's eudaimonism is what I call Socratic. Some want to extract from Republic IX or the Laws some hedonism that might be in tension with Socratic eudaimonism ( citations ), and others want to extract from the Philebus a view like the one the Peripatetics developed ( citations ). By contrast, I am impressed by Socratic dialogues' frequent insistence that the goal is "living well" or "doing well" (Charmides 171e-172a, Crito 48b, Gorgias 507c; cf. Republic I 354a), and by Socrates' use of these phrases interchangeably with eudaimonia and being eudaimōn in the Euthydemus (278e-282d), and I do not see anything that requires Plato to retract these simple identifications of that for the sake of which we should act with virtuous activity. Obviously, though, this needs fuller argument elsewhere. 13 Kraut (1989) appeals to a discussion of exile in the Politics and argues that Aristotle is not a eudaimonist, and Whiting ( citation ) appeals to the discussion of friendship in the Nicomachean Ethics and argues the same. But there is a general reason resist these moves: if Plato embraced eudaimonism, then we should expect Aristotle to make more noise renouncing it. Besides those doubters, so-called "inclusivists" readers ( citations ) attribute to Aristotle the view I call Peripatetic eudaimonism (see note 00 above). But the Peripatetics and inclusivists misread Aristotle. Aristotle avows again and again that eudaimonia is virtuous activity, even as he is working hard to show that this view can embrace and even explain apparently conflicting platitudes concerning the

importance of external goods. (See especially λόγος at EN I 8 1098b20 and 1098b31, I 9 1099b25, and I 10

Three points matter. First, only the consequentialist sort of eudaimonism offers a simple solution

to the problem of advising fools. It says that one should do whatever best promotes one's own

eudaimonia, and it is clear where to look to determine what a fool should do, even if the

determination might be difficult and require judgment. The Socratic sort of eudaimonism, by

contrast, simply says that one should act virtuously, and so it plainly faces the problem of

advising fools.

Second, consequentialist eudaimonism's simple solution to the problem of advising fools

will not appeal to most adherents of "virtue ethics." Adherents of "virtue ethics" believe that a

virtuous person must value his or her virtuous actions for their own sake. Consequentialist

eudaimonism cannot directly accommodate this requirement, because according to it, a virtuous

action is valuable only because it brings about eudaimonia as a state of affairs separate from the

action. The virtue theorists on whose behalf I am toiling today do not want to embrace this

view.^15

1100b11; but also EN I 8 1099a29-31, I 10 1100a13-14, and I 13 1102a5- 6. Brown (2006b) discusses these.) But Aristotle does complicate his identification of eudaimonia with virtuous activity by adding that it must be virtuous activity temporally extended over a complete life. (See EN I 7 1098a18-20, with I 10 1101a16, X 7 1177b25, and Brown 2006b, 224 - 225. Cf. EN III 2 1111b28-29 with Brown 2006b, 239 - 240 .) It is worth emphasizing that a Socratic eudaimonist can reject Aristotle's addendum; indeed, some Stoics might have. Plutarch offers contrasting testimony at Stoic. rep. 1046c-e and Comm. not. 1061f-1062a. (^14) Mitsis (1988) and Annas (1993) argue otherwise. But I am struck by the fact that Epicurus finds mere instrumental value in so many of the things that most eudaimonists consider intrinsically valuable, including friendship (see Brown 2002 and 2009) and philosophical activity (see Brown 2008). I also suspect that Epicurus cannot consider eudaimonia to be virtuous activity because he takes it to be pleasure and he takes pleasure to be a passive condition (pathos). Indeed, he must take pleasure to be a pathos because, on his view, if it were not passive, it would not be an inerrant guide for action as sense-perception is an inerrant guide for judgments. But, again, this requires more argument elsewhere. (^15) One might suggest that consequentialist eudaimonism can accommodate the requirement that a virtuous agent find his or her virtuous actions intrinsically valuable. One might insist that nobody can successfully act for the sake of their eudaimonia except by accepting the fiction that virtuous actions are intrinsically valuable. Alternatively, one might construe consequentialist eudaimonism as a "two-level" view, according to which (level one) a person should be virtuous because it best brings about his or her own eudaimonia and (level two) a virtuous person should value virtue for its own sake. (O'Keefe (2001) attributes such a view to Epicurus, but I believe that RS 25 rules it out.) But these are also unlikely to appeal to the fans of "virtue ethics." These fans typically believe that virtue requires clear-eyed, correct apprehension of the value of one's actions and why they have that value. Relatedly, ancient eudaimonists desired that the agent's pursuit of his own good directly give

perform some actions the virtuous person would perform and because he should perform some

actions the virtuous person would not. The Socratic eudaimonist plainly has a problem advising

fools.

One might try to help the Socratic eudaimonists by investigating more closely their idea

of virtuous activity.

17

The Socratics broadly agree that virtuous activity is wise activity,

18

that

wise activity is activity from wisdom, and that wisdom is a coherent set of psychological

commitments. The first two of those identities are widely recognized, but the third is perhaps

not. To see why the Socratics identified wisdom with psychological coherence, consider

Socrates. Socrates' pursuit of wisdom largely consists in examining himself and others to see

whether his or their commitments (beliefs, desires, emotions) cohere. When he finds

inconsistency, he is certain that those he is examining fail to have knowledge. But what must he

think about wisdom if he takes himself to be pursuing wisdom in this way? Socrates could not

be the paradigmatic philosopher if the coherence he tests for and tries to cultivate were not at

least plausibly linked with knowledge or wisdom. His principal followers, and most clearly the

Stoics, actually identify wisdom with psychological coherence.

19 (^17) One may contrast what follows with Hursthouse's (1999) strategy of filling in the account of virtuous actions by reference to "v-rules." (^18) Aristotle would want the qualification that "fully virtuous" or "virtuous activity strictly speaking" is wise activity (EN VI 13). Plato and the early Stoics are typically less accommodating of "ordinary virtue," but notice Plato's notion of "political courage" (politikē andreia, Rep. IV 430c2-4). (^19) See Brown 2006a. It is true that Socrates disavows knowledge (Gorgias 509a) even as he also claims for himself some measure of coherence (Gorgias 481d-482c), but this does not require that he conceive of knowledge as something entirely other than the coherence he has. It would be well explained by his thinking that knowledge does (or even might) require more of the coherence he has. In any case, Plato runs with the conception of wisdom and knowledge as coherence, insisting that wisdom appears only in the person who sees how things hang together as one (e.g., Rep. VII 537c6-7, Phdr. 270c1-2 with Brown 2003) and whose soul hangs together as one (e.g., Rep IV 443c9-444a2). Aristotle characterizes the knower as unpersuadable (A.Po. A2 72b3-4) and the wise as knowing everything so far as possible (Metaph. A2 982a8-9). The Stoic identification of knowledge with a coherent psychology is clearest, though: they define knowledge, whether a cognitive grasp, a system of grasps, or a state of receiving impressions, as secure, stable, and unshakeable by reason or argument (Stobaeus II 7.5l 73,19-74,1; Diog. Laert. VII 47; Sextus, M VII 151; Pseudo-Galen SVF 2.93; Philo SVF 2.95; and Cicero, Acad I 41-42, who attributes the account to Zeno of Citium).

This adds some flesh to Socratic eudaimonism, but alas, it does not immediately solve the

problem of advising fools. For a fool—one who cannot be helped by the advice that he act as a

wise person would—surely lacks the wisdom of a coherent mind and is thus not going to be

helped by the advice that he act so as to express and sustain a coherent set of commitments.

Fortunately, there is evidence that Socratic eudaimonists were aware of this problem.

Perhaps the most striking piece of evidence comes in Seneca's 116th Moral Letter. Seneca is

discussing the question of whether it is better to have moderate passions or none at all (Ep. Mor.

116.1), and he is addressing the concern that while it might be easy for a sage to live without

passions, it is hard to see how one of us could do so (Ep. Mor. 116.4 and 116.7-8). He notes,

Panaetius seems to me to have responded elegantly to some young man who asked him

whether the sage would become a lover: "Concerning the sage, we shall see; but you and

I, who are currently far from the sage, should not commit ourselves to fall into a

condition that is disordered, uncontrolled, enslaved to another, contemptible to itself. For

if [our beloved] shows regard for us, we would be excited by the kindness; [but] if [our

beloved] scorns us, we would be kindled by our pride. Ease in love hurts us as much as

difficulty; we are captured by the ease, and we struggle with the difficulty. Therefore,

knowing our weakness, let us remain quiet. Let us not commit a weak mind to wine, or

beauty, or flattery, or anything that attracts us seductively." What Panaetius said about

love in response to the questioner I say about all passions. Insofar as we can, let us step

back from slippery places; even on dry ground it is hard enough to take a sturdy stand.

20 (^20) Ep.Mor. 116.5-6 (trans. with some borrowing from Gummere 1917-1925): Eleganter mihi videtur Panaetius respondisse adulescentulo cuidam quaerenti an sapiens amaturus esset. 'De sapiente' inquit 'videbimus: mihi et tibi, qui adhuc a sapiente longe absumus, non est committendum ut incidamus in rem commotam, inpotentem, alteri emancupatam, vilem sibi. Sive enim nos respicit, humanitate eius inritamur, sive contempsit, superbia accendimur. Aeque facilitas amoris quam difficultas nocet: facilitate capimur, cum difficultate certamus. Itaque conscii nobis inbecillitatis nostrae quiescamus; nec vino infirmum animum committamus nec formae nec

According to this sensible advice, each of us should act not as the virtuous person would in our

circumstances but as we need to act so as to become virtuous.

But this introduces an apparent shift in the structure of the Socratics' ethical theory.

Perhaps the sage acts for the sake of eudaimonia simply by (partly or wholly) instantiating it, but

fools, who cannot do this, should act for the sake of eudaimonia by acting so as to become

virtuous agents. The Socratics might accept some consequentialism after all!

In what follows, I argue that this is not the best way to understand the Socratics' advice to

fools. I attend more closely to the Stoics' psychotherapy to show that they mean to advise us to

act so as to approximate the virtuous agent and not (or at least not simply) to act so as to bring

about our being a virtuous agent.

4. Stoic Psychotherapy

Stoic psychotherapy is widely misunderstood. According to a common misconception,

Stoics conceive of passions as false evaluative judgments and so conceive of the practical aim of

psychotherapy as replacing them with true evaluative judgments.^22 This is a double mistake.

First, passions, according to the Stoics, can be true evaluative judgments. Cicero records

an especially vivid case: Alcibiades feels distress (aegritudo) about his vice and desires to be

made virtuous by Socrates.

23

Of course, by a Stoic's lights, Alcibiades is vicious, his vice is bad

(^22) Even scholars who know better say that passions are false judgments. Compare Brennan 1998, 48-51, with Brennan 1998, 31. The former passage does an excellent job explaining what is wrong with the latter, and includes a fine discussion of Cicero, Tusc. III 77-78. For an apology, see Brennan 2003, 290. (^23) Tusc. III 77: For what shall we say—when Socrates, as we are told, persuaded Alcibiades that he was not at all a man and that there was no difference, though he was born in the highest class, between him and any porter, and when Alcibiades, distressed, tearfully begged Socrates to give him virtue and drive baseness away,—what shall we say, Cleanthes? Surely not that there was nothing bad in the cause which made Alcibiades feel distress? (Quid enim dicemus, cum Socrates Alcibiadi persuasisset, ut accepimus, eum nihil hominis esse nec quidquam inter Alcibiadem summo loco natum et quemvis baiulum interesse, cum se Alcibiades adflictaret

for him, and it would be good for him to become virtuous. His judgments are all true. But he is

experiencing the passion of distress nonetheless, and this distress is bad for him and could

substantially interfere with his progress (by, say, discouraging him from hanging out with

Socrates, who reminds him of his vice).

Chrysippus defines passions not as false judgments but as weak ones.

24

Weak judgments

contrast with the strong judgments that a sage necessarily makes (Stobaeus II 7.11m 112,1- 2 ).

The sage's judgments are strong because they are all pieces of knowledge, that is, secure, stable,

and unshakeable by reason or argument (citations in n. 19 above). So the strength of a judgment

comes from its larger network of judgments whose contents are all inferentially related: all the

knower's judgments hold every one of the knower's judgments in place, unshakeable by

argument. By implication, the fool's judgments are all weak because the fool's network of

judgments contains mistakes or gaps and so does not hold any one of the fool's judgments

unshakeably in place (cf. Stobaeus II 7.11m 111,20-21). Even the fool's true judgments are

weak, because of the network in which they are insufficiently held in place; they are shakable

and insecure, outside of one's perfect control.

25 lacrimansque Socrati supplex esset, ut sibi virtutem traderet turpitudinemque depelleret, quid dicemus, Cleanthe? num in illa re, quae aegritudine Alcibiadem adficiebat, mali nihil fuisse?) (^24) See the canonical definitions of passions cited below, along with Stobaeus II 7.10 82,22-89,2 and Cicero, Tusc. IV 15: "The judgment that we have included in all the above definitions they want to be weak assent" [Opinationem autem, quam in omnes definitions superiors inclusimus, volunt esse imbecillam adsensionem]. (^25) Frede (1986) rightly saw that the way one judges is crucial to whether one's judgment is a passion, but he did not stress that this way is determined by the relation between this judgment and one's other judgments. He also wrongly inferred that the content of the judgment was not also crucial, as the Stoic definitions of generic passions (cited below) suggest they are. So according to Frede's Stoics grief is not necessarily the judgment, e.g., that Socrates' death is bad for me but can be the judgment that Socrates is dead, judged in a certain way. In fact, however, Chrysippus thinks that it must be the judgment that Socrates' death is bad for me, judged in a certain way (namely, weakly and, as we shall see, freshly). Frede overreaches from two pieces of evidence. First, based on an argument by Arcesilaus against the Stoics, he maintains that the Stoics understand judgment in such a way that the judger assents to an impression, and not merely to the propositional content of an impression. But Arcesilaus says, "If the katalepsis is assent to a kataleptic impression, then it is non-existent, since, first, assent is not to an impression but to rational content (for assents are to propositions)…" [Sextus, M VII 154: εἴπερ τε ἡ κατάληψις καταληπτικῆς φαντασίας συγκατάθεσις ἐστιν, ἀνυπαρκτός ἐστι, πρῶτον μὲν ὅτι ἡ συγκατάθεσις οὐ πρὸς φαντασίαν γίνεται ἀλλὰ πρὸς λόγον (τῶν γὰρ ἀξιωμάτων εἰσὶν αἱ συγκαταθέσεις)…].

"That would be good (or bad) for me," and as the impulses (actions) necessarily joined to these

fresh, weak evaluative judgments.

29

Understood in this way, passions outstrip my control (they

are weak, unstable, shakable), and they move me. This is why the Stoics characterize passions as

"excessive" and "contrary to right and natural reason."

30

By now, we can see the second way in which the usual view of Stoic psychopathology

and psychotherapy is mistaken. Not only does it misconstrue passions as false evaluative

judgments; it misconstrues the therapy as the attempt to replace them with true evaluative

judgments. Cleanthes might have thought something like this (Cicero, Tusc. III 76-77), which is

why Cicero raises the case of Alcibiades against him. The trick with Alcibiades is not to get him

to think that his vice is good for him or that becoming virtuous would not be good. Rather, the

point is to break Alcibiades of the thought that he should beat himself up about his vice, for this

is the thought that might cause him to avoid Socrates. Alcibiades' therapy needs to target not his

passion but the most problematic manifestations of his passion.

Chrysippus seems to have favored this sort of psychotherapy generally. As Cicero

reports, "Chrysippus thinks the main thing in consoling is to remove that [viz., the second]

judgment from the mourner, if the mourner thinks that he is discharging a just and obligatory

duty."

31

Chrysippus, in other words, does not try to remove the passion of grief from a

(^29) See especially the canonical definitions of the four generic passions (pleasure, pain, desire, and fear) at Andronicus, On Passions 1; Cicero's Tusculan Disputations IV 14; Stobaeus II 7.10b 90,7-18. Galen separates the part of the definition in terms of an evaluative judgment (Galen, PHP IV 2.1) from the part of the definition in terms of an impulse (Galen, PHP IV 2.5), but he presumably does this because he wants to insist Chrysippus contradicts himself. Inwood (1985, 146-147) suggests, on the basis of some silence in Andronicus, On Passions 1; Cicero, Tusculan Disputations IV 14; and Stobaeus II 7.10 88,22-89,3, that only distress and pleasure must be fresh judgments, and not fear and desire. But this misses Stobaeus II 7.10b 90,7-18, which attributes freshness to fear's judgment. We can also explain the silence, if the Stoics assume that the motivational force of evaluative judgments about future goods and bads for me are more obvious (and less likely to wane) than the motivational force of evaluative judgments about present goods and bads for me. (^30) See Stobaeus II 7.10 88,8-10 with 7.10a 89,5 and 89,14-16, and cf. Galen, PHP IV 2.14-18. (^31) Cicero, Tusc. III 76: Chrysippus autem caput esse censet in consolando detrahere illam opinionem maerenti, si se officio fungi putet iusto atque debito.

mourner—the evaluative judgment that something bad has happened, which (if fresh) necessarily

prompts some impulse—but tries to remove the judgment that it is appropriate to mourn, to have

this particular mourning impulse (instead of a mere sinking feeling).^32 This will mitigate the

effect of the grief, and make it more manageable. Of course, this is not the end goal for

Chrysippean therapy: he wants mourners to progress to the point at which they accept the Stoic

view that the loss of a friend is not something bad for them. But Chrysippus thinks that

psychotherapy needs to attend to a larger network of commitments than simply their belief about

something bad, and in particular it needs to attend to how intentional actions fit into this larger

network.

This attention to actions and a broader network is what Seneca likes about Panaetius'

advice to the young man looking for love. Panaetius tells the youngster to turn away from love,

(^32) Sorabji (2000, esp. 32-33) and Graver (2002, 90-94 with appendix C) argue that Chrysippus' is eliminating the passion of grief by removing the judgment that it is appropriate to mourn. This seems to me impossible: if the evaluative judgment is fresh, it must entail some impulsive judgment or another, and all Chrysippus can do is change the impulsive judgment and hope that by changing the impulsive judgment he can induce the evaluative judgment to go stale (and thereby extinguish the passion). Graver finds Cicero, Tusc. III 61 ad fin. and 68- 70 especially telling for her claim, but I suspect that these passages represent some Ciceronian flourishes and not Chrysippus' view. Sorabji offers four reasons. The first, that a passion must involve both an evaluative judgment and an impulsive judgment (33), is correct, but it says nothing about the possible connections between these judgments. The second, that the evaluative judgment can be true but passion's judgments cannot be wholly true (32), misconstrues the defect of passionate judgments. The third, that the impulsive judgment is the main target of Chrysippean therapy (32, cf. 176-179) is correct but does not show that this side of Chrysippean therapy is supposed to extirpate passions. And the fourth is the evidence of Galen, PHP IV 7.12-14 (33, cf. 109 - 112): "Chrysippus also testifies in Book Two of On Passions that passions soften in time even though the beliefs remain that something evil has happened to them, when he writes thus: 'One might inquire also about the lessening of distress, how it happens, whether with change in some belief or with all the beliefs continuing, and why this will be.' Then, proceeding, he says, 'I think belief of this sort remains, that the actually present thing is bad, but when it grows older, the contraction and, as I believe, the impulse to the contraction lessen.'" (Ὅτι δ' ἐν τῷ χρόνῳ μαλάττεται τὰ πάθη, κἂν αἱ δόξαι μένωσι τοῦ κακόν τι αὐτοῖς γεγονέναι, καὶ ὁ Χρύσιπποω ἐν τῷ δευτέρῳ Περὶ Παθῶν μαρτυρεῖ γράφων ὧδε· "ζητήσαι δ' ἄν τις καὶ περὶ τῆς ἀνέσεως τῆς λύπης, πῶς φίνεται, πότερον δόξης τινὸς μετακινουμένης ἢ πασῶν διαμενουσῶν, καὶ διὰ τί τοῦτ' ἔσται." εἶτ' ἐπιφέρων φησί, "δοκεῖ δέ μοι ἡ μὲν τοιαύτη δόχα διαμένειν, ὅτι κακὸν αὐτὸ ὃ δὴ πάρεστιν, ἐγχρονιζομένης δ' ἀνὶεσθαι ἡ συστολὴ καὶ ὡς οἷμαι ἡ ἐπὶ τὴν συστολὴν ὁρμή ) Sorabji may be right to say that Chrysippus here links the fading of a passion ("the contraction") with the changing of the impulsive judgment ("the impulse to the contraction"). But I note that these occur as the evaluative judgment grows stale ("when it grows older"). So Chrysippus could well insist that the passion will lessen to the point of dissipation only if the evaluative judgment is so stale that it necessitates no impulsive judgment, and even in this case (which goes further than Chrysippus entertains here), the passion can be rekindled should the evaluative judgment become fresh again.

evaluative judgments or related behavioral commitments. Second, how problematic these related

judgments are varies. If the fool is inflamed by physical beauty with a desire for a significant

other, he is in more trouble than if he recognizes the potential for virtue with the desire to make a

new friend but does so without a perfectly coherent set of psychological commitments. So

exactly what therapy the fool needs will vary. Panaetius is addressing someone he is sure is far

from wisdom, and so he recommends sweeping behavioral safeguards. But he might well,

despite his rhetoric ("we are far from the sage"), allow himself to be moved by erotic love to try

to make a friend.

This approach to behavioral psychotherapy, common to Chrysippus, Panaetius, and

Seneca, manifests two commitments. First, the concern is to mitigate the damage to one's

psychological coherence. Stoic psychotherapy targets passionate actions that wreak havoc on the

patient's mental life and seek to replace those actions with less damaging swellings and

contractions. Second, Stoic psychotherapy targets passions by locating them in a broader

network of commitments, including evaluations and intentions. For Stoic psychotherapy to

succeed, the adviser must recommend an action that expresses and sustains the patient's mental

condition better than any alternative.

It is true that the ultimate goal of such therapy is virtue. In some sense, then, the therapy

must be judged successful or not by whether it promotes this ultimate goal. But the careful work

of Chrysippean therapy is not well characterized by saying that the Stoic recommends that one

choose the action, whatever action, that best promotes her becoming virtuous. Rather, the Stoic

recommends an action based on its fit with the agent's mental conditions, his or her overall

psychological commitments. The agent is to approximate what the sage does, not by mimicking

the sage's behavior, but by mimicking the virtuousness of the sage's behavior, that is, by finding

a fit between his action and the rest of his commitments that approximates the fit between the

sage's action and the rest of the sage's commitments.

5. A Principle for Advising Fools?

Stoic psychopathology and psychotherapy offer subtle advice to the fool. On this view,

all of us should try to act virtuously in the sense that all of us should try to act in a way that

expresses and sustains a coherent mind. Those of us who have perfectly coherent minds thereby

act virtuously. Those of us who do not have perfectly coherent minds can only express and

sustain an approximately coherent mind. More exactly, our action can fit our mind in a way that

only approximates the way that the virtuous person's fits hers.

According to my suggestion, then, "virtue ethics" can find an answer to the problem of

advising fools by trading its general principle (Act as the virtuous person would in one's

circumstances) for a subtly different eudaimonist principle (Act for the sake of one's virtuous

activity) and by recognizing two distinct ways of acting for the sake of one's virtuous activity.

One can act for the sake of virtuous activity as a virtuous person by performing a bit of virtuous

activity, and one can do it as a fool by approximating virtuous activity. To give some content to

this notion of approximating virtuous activity, advocates of "virtue ethics" can follow the

Socratics further by identifying virtue with psychological coherence and the approximation of

virtuous activity with the approximation of a virtuous action's fit with the rest of the agent's

psychology.

This answer is, at least in broad outline, plausible. But it obviously needs more

development. It requires an account of psychological coherence and especially of degrees of