Docsity
Docsity

Prepare for your exams
Prepare for your exams

Study with the several resources on Docsity


Earn points to download
Earn points to download

Earn points by helping other students or get them with a premium plan


Guidelines and tips
Guidelines and tips

A Historical Overview of Brain Localization Theories from Flourens to Lashley, Study Guides, Projects, Research of History

An historical account of theories of brain localization from the work of Pierre Flourens to Karl Lashley. Flourens is considered the founder of field theory, having shown that different parts of the brain have distinct functions. However, his theories were based on limited techniques and assumptions about psychological processes. Later researchers, such as Ferrier and Lashley, built upon Flourens' work but with more refined techniques and a better understanding of neuroanatomy. Lashley's field theory challenged Associationist psychology and introduced the principles of equipotentiality and mass action.

Typology: Study Guides, Projects, Research

2021/2022

Uploaded on 09/12/2022

unknown user
unknown user 🇬🇧

1 / 14

Toggle sidebar

This page cannot be seen from the preview

Don't miss anything!

bg1
THEORIES
OF
BRAIN
LOCALIZATION
FROM
FLOURENS
TO
LASHLEY
by
BARBARA
TIZARD
Introduction
A
history
of
theories
of
localization
of
function
in
the
brain
can
be
found
more
or
less
briefly
outlined
in
Boring
(I929
and
I950)
and
Lashley
(I929).
Both
writers
point
out
that
all
such
theories
can
be
broadly
divided
into
two
types-localization
theories,
which
hold
that
specific
functions
are
controlled
by
specific
parts
of
the
brain,
and
field
theories,
which
hold
that
the
brain
acts
as
a
single
functional
unit.
It
is
said
that,
historically,
a
swing
of
the
pen-
dulum
tends
to
occur
between
these
two
positions.
At
one
period
the
majority
of
informed
opinion
holds
a
localization
theory,
but
a
generation
later
this
tends
to
be
considered
distinctly
unorthodox.
Too
much
can
be
made
of
this
distinction.
Localization
and
field
theories,
as
defined
above,
have
not
been
held
since
the
time
of
Gall.
The
first
achievement
of
Flourens,
usually
regarded
as
the
founder
of
field
theory,
was
to
show
that
the
different
parts
of
the
brain
have
specific
functions:
he
claimed
that
only
the
hemispheres
act
as
a
single
functional
unit.
Later
field
theorists
further
restricted
this
claim.
Nevertheless,
the
distinction
between
localization
theorists
and
field
theorists
is
broadly
valid.
The
purpose
of
this
article
is
to
examine
the
factors
responsible
for
the
'swing
of
the
pendulum',
that
is,
for
the
development
and
general
acceptance
of
successive
theories.
Two
factors
are
shown
to
be
important.
The
development
of
a
new
theory
of
localization
depends
partly
on
the
development
of
new
and
more
refined
techniques
of
investigation,
and
partly
on
the
nature
of
current
psychological
preconceptions.
This
is
because
such
a
theory
must
involve
assumptions
about
psychological
processes
and
brain
function,
and
the
models
of
brain
function
are
themselves
determined
by
psychological
preconceptions.
In
the
past
these
assumptions
have
been
explicit.
It
is
argued
that
the
implicit
assumptions
of
contemporary
localization
theory
could
usefully
be
examined,
and
brought
into
line
with
contemporary
psychology.
L
Flourens'
Field
Theory
Theories
of
localization
of
function
can
be
traced
back
as
far
as
Aristotle,
but
the
work
of
Pierre
Flourens
(1794-I867)
was
the
first
to
be
based
on
experiment,
and
Flourens
is
today
recognized
as
the
founder
of
the
modern
field
theory
of
brain
function.
He
was
undoubtedly
a
great
physiologist.
His
experiments
were
systematic,
his
observations
were
always
repeated,
and
they
were
made
on
a
number
of
subjects.
Using
the
methods
of
extirpation
and
stimulation
he
was
the
first
132
pf3
pf4
pf5
pf8
pf9
pfa
pfd
pfe

Partial preview of the text

Download A Historical Overview of Brain Localization Theories from Flourens to Lashley and more Study Guides, Projects, Research History in PDF only on Docsity!

THEORIES OF BRAIN LOCALIZATION

FROM FLOURENS TO LASHLEY

by

BARBARA TIZARD

Introduction A history of theories of localization of function in the brain can be found

more or less briefly outlined in Boring (I929 and^ I950) and Lashley^ (I929).

Both writers point out that all such theories can be^ broadly divided^ into two

types-localization theories, which hold^ that^ specific functions^ are^ controlled

by specific parts of the brain, and^ field^ theories,^ which^ hold^ that the^ brain

acts as a single functional unit.^ It is^ said^ that,^ historically,^ a^ swing^ of the pen-

dulum tends to occur between these^ two^ positions. At^ one^ period^ the^ majority

of informed opinion holds^ a^ localization theory,^ but^ a^ generation^ later this

tends to be considered distinctly unorthodox.

Too much can be made of this^ distinction.^ Localization^ and^ field theories,^ as

defined above, have not^ been^ held^ since the^ time of Gall. The^ first^ achievement

of Flourens, usually regarded as^ the^ founder^ of field^ theory,^ was^ to^ show^ that

the different parts of^ the^ brain^ have^ specific functions:^ he claimed that^ only

the hemispheres act^ as^ a^ single functional^ unit.^ Later^ field theorists further

restricted this claim. Nevertheless, the distinction between localization theorists

and field theorists is broadly valid. The purpose of this article is to examine the

factors responsible for the 'swing of the pendulum', that is, for the development

and general acceptance of successive theories.

Two factors are shown to be important. The development of a new theory

of localization depends partly on the development of new and more refined

techniques of investigation, and partly on the nature of current psychological

preconceptions. This is because such a theory must involve assumptions about

psychological processes and brain function, and the^ models^ of^ brain^ function

are themselves determined by psychological preconceptions. In^ the^ past these

assumptions have been explicit. It is argued that the^ implicit assumptions of

contemporary localization theory could usefully be^ examined, and^ brought

into line with contemporary psychology.

L Flourens' Field Theory

Theories of localization of function^ can^ be^ traced back^ as^ far^ as^ Aristotle,

but the work of Pierre^ Flourens^ (1794-I867) was^ the first^ to^ be based^ on

experiment, and Flourens^ is^ today^ recognized^ as^ the^ founder^ of^ the^ modern

field theory of brain function.

He was undoubtedly a^ great physiologist. His^ experiments were^ systematic,

his observations were^ always^ repeated,^ and^ they^ were^ made^ on^ a^ number of

subjects. Using the methods of extirpation and^ stimulation^ he^ was^ the^ first

132

Theories of Brain Localizationfrom Flourens to Lashley

to show experimentally that different parts of the nervous system have different

functions. He concluded that the function of the spinal cord is conduction, that movement is controlled by the cerebellum, the vital functions by the medulla, and perception, memory, and will by the hemispheres. In 1824 he put forward the first scientifically based theory of equipotentiality

within the hemispheres.

All sensations, all perceptions, and all volition occupy concurrently the same seat in these organs. The faculty of sensation, perception, and volition is then essentially one faculty.

He was the first to (^) state the principles of (^) equivalence of structure and (^) of mass action.

As long as not too much of the lobes is removed, they may in due time regain the exercise of their functions. Passing certain limits, however, the animal regains them only imperfectly, and passing these new limits it does not regain them at all. Finally, if one sensation comes back, all come back. If one faculty reappears, they all reappear.... This shows that each of these organs is only a single organ.

Again, like later field theorists, he emphasized the integration of the nervous

system.

In (^) the last analysis ... all the essential and various parts of the nervous system have specific properties, proper functions, distinct effects, and^ in^ spite of^ this marvellous^ diversity they constitute nevertheless a^ unified system. When one point in the^ nervous^ system becomes excited, it excites all others; one point irritated, irritates all. There is^ community of reaction. Unity is the great reigning principle (Flourens, 1824).

All this, of course, constitutes a field theory of brain function more thorough-

going than any held since. No one today would be prepared to support the

proposition that there is no localization of sensory function in the cortex, and

that 'if one (sense) comes back, all come back'. Indeed, as will be shown,

there was a good deal of evidence to the contrary available at^ the^ time. Never-

theless, Flourens' theories were at once generally accepted and remained

orthodox doctrine for over forty years. There were two^ important reasons for

this. Firstly, the techniques of stimulation and extirpation were too crudely

developed to reveal much localization of function, and the^ knowledge of^ neuro-

anatomy then available too limited. The only parts of the brain^ distinguished

were medulla, corpora quadrigemina, cerebellum, and^ the^ hemispheres; it was not known in^ what way, if^ any, grey and white^ matter^ differed^ in^ function.

In the following experiment, for^ example, on^ which^ Flourens^ based his^ principle

of equipotentiality, it is certain that he must have extirpated more than the

hemispheres, and that^ septic and oedematous^ processes must^ have^ resulted^ in

generalized damage of an unknown extent. He removed, 'layer by layer',

different parts of both cerebral lobes of a pigeon, and found that^ the^ animal's

sight weakened with^ each^ new^ extirpation until it^ was^ totally lost, and that

'from the moment that sight was gone, hearing was gone too; and with it went

all intellectual and sensory faculties'.

'

Theories ofBrain Localizationfrom Flourens to Lashley

anatomist, phrenology was as speculative a doctrine as the orthodox theory of

the sensorium. It had tremendous popular appeal but it was bitterly attacked

by most scientists and philosophers as irreverent and materialistic because

incompatible with the concept of brain as a sensorium. Flourens' work was

hailed as a convincing experimental refutation of this heresy, and a validation

of orthodox concepts.

Consequently the observations that were incompatible with equipotentiality

of the cortex were disregarded. Bell (I 774-I842) had argued that the fact that

separate nerve tracts lead to separate parts of the cortex indicates that these

have distinct functions. It was pointed out by some that the insane (^) are not

usually blind and deaf. The experiments of Fransois Pourfour de Petit were

forgotten. This eighteenth-century French surgeon had adduced strong evidence

that the control of movements of one side of the body is localized in the hemi-

sphere of the other side. Contralateral hemiplegia was at the time ascribed to

loss of fluid from the contralateral ventricle, which moved into the wounded

ventricle to replace its lost fluid, with a resultant loss of power on the contra-

lateral side. Petit opened the skull of an officer who had died from a rapier

thrust beneath his right orbit, and who before death had sustained a complete

left hemiplegia; he found pus pouring from a right anterior abscess, but nothing

amiss in either ventricle. After a number of similar post-mortem observations

he decided to operate on dogs, destroying various parts of their brain through

a trephine hole, noting their loss of power, and then examining their brains.

He observed^ that^ paralysis of the opposite side always ensued, and dissection

led him to the discovery of the decussation of the pyramids (Rawson, I927).

III. A new concept of brain

It has been argued above that, for an empirically based theory of specificity

to develop, more refined techniques would be needed than were available to

Flourens, and, for such a theory to be generally accepted, the orthodox concept

of brain would have to be abandoned. The latter change occurred first. The

essential preliminary to the more detailed assumptions of localization theory

was an attempt to account for the workings of the nervous system in purely

physical terms. The earlier semi-scholastic conception ofthe brain as a sensorium

where mind interacted with body, the nerves being passive conductors of animal

spirits, was replaced by an explicit determination to 'constitute physiology on a

chemico-physical foundation' (Helmholtz, I847, quoted in Boring). In I

du Bois Reymond demonstrated the electrical nature of the nervous impulse

and in^ I850 Helmholtz measured its speed. During the next decade reaction

times began to^ be measured. No wonder that Muller hesitated to accept these

discoveries with their implication that the nervous system is wholly orderly and

physical.

During this period, too, it was discovered that the grey matter of the brain

is cellular, that the white matter is fibrous, and that the fibres begin and end

in the grey cells. The contemporary model of the brain, based on these

observations and the new (^) preconceptions, is described (^) by the (^) psychologist,

'

Barbara (^) Tizard

Alexander Bain (I8I8-I903), in his book, The Senses and the Intellect, I855. He

states in his (^) preface:

Conceiving that the time has now come when many of the startling discoveries of Physiolo- gists relative to the nervous system should find a recognised place in the Science of Mind, I have devoted a separate chapter to the Physiology of the Brain and Nerves.

In this chapter he compares the nervous system to a telegraph system, with

a general terminus, the brain, from which wires proceed to (^) substations, from

which further wires proceed. The function of the nerves is solely to transmit

impulses. The brain is also compared to a voltaic battery.

The brain is not a sensorium where impressions are poured in and stored up. A stimulus or sensation acting on the brain exhausts itself in the production of a number of transmitted currents or influences.... The revival of the impression is the setting of the currents anew.... No currents, no mind (Bain, 1855).

Later, he expounds Flourens' doctrine of equipotentiality, combining this

with the concept of the brain as a voltaic cell. Nevertheless, the change in

attitude to cerebral functioning which was essential for a revision of Flourens'

doctrine had occurred. 'No currents, no mind' is an assumption of startlingly

materialist implications, compared with Muller's theory of twenty years earlier.

IV. The era of localization theory

The first outright opponent of the principle of homogeneity was Broca

(I824-80). It is interesting that Broca was a pupil of Bouillaud, Professor of

Clinical Medicine at La Charite, one of the few academic champions of

phrenology. Bouillant had offered a sum ofmoney to anyone who could produce

the brain of an individual who had lost his speech, and in whom the anterior

lobes presented no lesions. Broca found at the autopsy of a man whom he had

recently examined and discovered to have no defect except inability to speak,

a lesion at the base of the third frontal convolution of the left hemisphere. He

announced in^ i86i^ that this^ was the^ centre for speech, and drew broader

conclusions.

I believe in the principle of localisation ... the totality of the convolutions does not con- stitute a single organ, but many organs or many groups oforgans, and there are in the cerebrum large discrete regions corresponding to large discrete mental functions (Broca, I86i).

This (^) generalization was based on rather (^) inadequate evidence, since, as Marie

showed later, of Broca's two original patients one had further lesions involving

Wernicke's zone, and the second had a generalized cerebral wasting. He does

not seem to have developed a theory significantly different from Gall's, and he

would probably have attracted little attention had the (^) opposition to Flourens not then become general. I

Barbara (^) Tizard

the hypothesis of circumscribed centres for special functions is^ untenable,^ and that^ there^ is no area of the cortex exclusively concerned with sight, hearing, smell, taste,^ touch^ ... or the higher fimctions.

V. The assumptions of nineteenth-century localization theory

Goltz, however, was in an^ unpopular minority,^ and^ it^ seems^ reasonable^ to

conclude that the physiologists of^ the^ last^ quarter of^ the^ nineteenth^ century

interpreted their^ results as^ indicating^ the^ existence^ of^ local centres because^ of a

prior conviction about the nature of the^ brain.^ An^ analytic trend^ was^ general

in scientific thought^ at^ that time.^ The^ cell^ theory,^ originated^ by^ Schleiden,^ was

developed by Virchow, Professor^ of^ Anatomy in Berlin.^ In I858^ he^ suggested

that a^ disease^ originates within^ a^ single^ cell, and is propagated^ by^ malignant cell formation.

Every animal [he wrote] is a^ sum of vital units, each^ of^ which^ possesses^ the^ full^ charac- teristics of life.... The composition of the major organism, the so-called individual,^ must^ be likened to a kind ofsocial arrangement or society, in^ which a^ number of^ separate^ existences^ are dependent upon one another, in such a^ way, however, that^ each individual^ possesses its^ own peculiar activity and carries out its own powers (Virchow, 1858).

This emphasis on the discrete and diverse functions of the cells was echoed by

the contemporary stress in psychology on the elementary particles of thought-

ideas. Mental processes were almost universally understood at this time in

terms of more and more complex associations of elementary ideas. The aim of

Associationism, in fact, was

to construct a^ psychology without^ a^ soul,^ by^ taking^ discrete^ ideas,^ and^ showing^ how,^ by^ their cohesions, such things as reminiscences, perceptions, emotions, volitions,^ passions,^ theories, and all the other furnishings of^ an^ individual's^ mind^ can^ be^ engendered^ (James,^ I891).

Hence the assumption by physiologists that they should look for the elementary

structures of the brain corresponding to its elementary functions.

The hypothesis generally held in the 'seventies, then, long before there was

much evidence to substantiate it, was that^ the^ cortex^ is^ the^ surface of^ projection

for every muscle and every sensitive^ point in^ the^ body. These different cortical

cells were held to represent the^ elementary ideas of sensation and motion^ of

which all mental^ processes are^ composed.^ The fibres between^ the cells^ represent

the association between^ ideas, hence there^ was^ thought^ to^ be^ a^ complete^ and

neat parallelism between^ brain processes^ and^ mental^ processes.

It is^ important^ to^ note^ the difference between^ the^ localization theory^ held

by physiologists of^ this^ period and^ the older^ phrenologists.^ The difference

depends on the development in the assumptions about^ mind^ and^ brain described

above. The later localizers held^ that^ elementary motor^ and^ sensory^ functions

were localized, but^ not^ the^ higher mental^ functions,^ still less^ traits^ such^ as

'hopefulness'. Some,^ for^ example,^ Ferrier,^ argued^ on^ mainly^ deductive^ grounds

that intelligence is dependent on the frontal^ lobes.^ Psychology, the^ argument

I

Theories of Brain Localization from Flourens to Lashley

ran, has shown that all the higher thought processes can be explained in terms

of the association of ideas, together with the power of attention. Intellectual

attention involves implicit head and eye movements, and hence depends on

the frontal lobes, which Ferrier had shown to be the centre for these movements

(i886).

Other physiologists, unable to confirm Ferrier's experimental findings,

adapted different theories. Munk, for example, argued that

intelligence has its seat everywhere in the cortex of the brain (^) and in no part in particular. Any lesion of the cerebral cortex whatsoever alters (^) intelligence, all (^) the more severely the more extensive the lesion, and this is (^) always due to the loss of its groups of images or representations, simple or complex, which had their (^) foundations in (^) the perceptions that belong to the injured cortical area (Munk, (^) -1890).

Thus, experimental observations similar to Flourens'-that intelligence does

not depend on any one part of the brain, and that the greater the lesion, the

greater the mental loss-were differently interpreted because of Munk's

different preconceptions about the brain and mental functioning. Instead of

concluding, like Flourens, that 'the faculties of perceiving, understanding, and

willing constitute a single function', he claimed that intelligence results from

co-ordination of a great many differently located elementary functions. Here

is a particularly clear illustration of the way in which assumptions about mental

processes have influenced the interpretation of findings in this field.

Later, however, it came to be generally accepted that the frontal lobes and

certain posterior parts of the brain were 'silent', and not projection areas. In

these areas the higher mental processes were said to be localized. Flechsig, the

originator of this theory, considered that the function of these areas was to

associate together the impressions received from the adjacent sensory and motor

areas. The frontal lobes, for example, lying between the olfactory and tactile

areas, combined the perceptions and memory traces of these areas. Flechsig was

primarily an anatomist, and the experimental investigation of the theory was

mainly the work of Bianchi, the last of this great school of physiologists. He

argued that

intelligence emanates from the (^) play of (^) sensory images ... and of infinite combinations of these and other images not sensory in character. I believe it is (^) permissible to (^) suppose that this vast co-ordination... has its seat in an (^) organ distinct from the organs of (^) perception (Bianchi, I922).

This organ he located in the frontal lobes, which until very recently have

continued to hold this (^) distinction. There was no question at (^) any time (^) during this

period, however, of a specific localization of traits akin to phrenology. Such a

doctrine was quite inconsistent with Associationist psychology, which held that

any complex function was the result of an interaction between many simple

functions, localized in various parts of the brain.

The influence of psychology on physiology at this period was remarkable.

Observations were scanty, and the main (^) emphasis in (^) discussing residual defect

'

Theories ofBrain Localizationfrom Flourens to Lashley

trials as the first learning. He performed control experiments, cutting the dura mater only, excising only one frontal lobe, and excising other lobes of the

brain (Franz, I907). The basic advances in methodology had been made-

that is, the use ofobjective tests that could be quantitatively scored, the procedure

of training, operating, then retraining, and the use of experimental control. To these Lashley (I929) added the use of enough animals to allow for statistical

analysis of results, and the attempt to assess the extent of lesion by post-mortem

examination.

Running fifty rats through mazes before and after cortical lesion, Lashley

found that the amount of impairment was roughly proportional to the extent

of cerebral lesion, and that the same amount of impairment in maze learning

is produced by equal amounts of destruction in any of the^ principal^ regions of

the cortex. From these observations he deduced first the Principle of Equipo-

tentiality, that the rat's cortex functions as a unit in maze learning and no one

part of it has special significance, and, secondly, the Law of Mass Action, that

the more cortex is available, the more rapid and accurate the learning. The

degree of deterioration after injury is closely related to the complexity of the

maze. These principles closely resemble Flourens', but Lashley restricted^ their

application. Not every habit in the^ rat^ is^ governed^ by these^ principles. Brightness

discrimination was disturbed only by lesions of the visual^ cortex, and^ he^ con-

cluded that it is only the more^ complex^ functions which^ are^ not^ localized.^ He

rejected the suggestion that his results might be due to the statistical effects of

different sensory losses, and insisted^ that 'the^ more^ complex^ functions^ ...^ are

largely carried^ out^ in^ independence^ of^ structural^ differentiation'^ (I929).

Lashley's findings met^ with^ a^ rather^ uncritical^ acceptance,^ at^ least^ among

psychologists. Hunter and Pavlov, however, suggested a different interpretation

of his results. There is, they pointed out, a good deal of evidence that maze

learning is dependent on sensory cues. Ifone sensory centre were destroyed, the

rat would utilize cues from another, so that, whilst no one lesion would destroy

the habit, it would be diminished roughly in proportion to the amount of

cerebral tissue destroyed, as fewer sensory cues were available (Hunter, I930;

Pavlov, I 94 I).

Lashley supported his conclusion that maze learning is dependent on some

unitary function ofthe cortex rather than on sensory cues by control experiments.

He showed that learning is unaffected by section of the kinaesthetic paths, by

enucleation of the eyes, or by removal of the occipital cortex from rats^ already

blinded before training. The evidence here is, however, conflicting. Other

experiments have shown that lesions of the dorsal spinal tracts^ have^ little effect

on behaviour cued to proprioceptive stimulation, which^ they argue are^ routed

round the lesion (Ghiselli, I936; Brown, I942). Finley (1941) removed^ about

I0 per cent of the rat's cortex, keeping within the striate area, and found that

in the dark these rats learnt mazes as well as normal rats, presumably by other

cues. Pickett (I942) trained blind^ rats^ in^ a^ kinaesthetic^ maze, and^ found^ that,

whilst anterior lesions produced some loss ofthe habit, there was little deteriora-

tion following striate lesions. These conflicting results cannot be reconciled

I4I

Barbara (^) Tizard

without further experiment, but it is clear that different hypotheses can be put

forward to^ account^ for the^ findings^ on^ which Lashley based his^ principles of

equipotentiality and^ mass^ action.

VII. Lashley's^ assumptions

There can be little doubt that Lashley, like his predecessors, was influenced

both in designing and interpreting his experiments by his prior conception of

brain action. He explicitly rejected the reflex, analytic model of the^ brain,

built up in the last half of the nineteenth century. He^ denied that^ integration

can be expressed in terms ofconnexions between specific^ neurones,^ and asserted

that brain function is not a summation ofdiverse functions, but^ a^ non-specialized

dynamic function of the tissue as a whole. He offered a^ tentative^ theory^ of brain

action, based on potential differences. A given ratio of^ stimulus intensities^ at

two peripheral points may, he suggested, establish^ a^ potential^ difference

between two corresponding areas in the cortex, resulting in a^ polarization^ of

the cortical field, essentially the same for different points within^ the^ areas.^ The

excitability of the final motor path would depend on^ the relative^ excitability

of the two areas (Lashley, I929).

This was the first attempt to give a physiological content^ to the^ principle^ of

'action commune'. Lashley was the first psychologist working with^ problems^ of

brain damage to interpret cortical dynamics in^ terms^ of^ field^ theory,^ and^ to

abandon Associationism.

In this he was largely influenced by Gestalt^ psychology.^ Wertheimer,^ the

founder ofGestalt psychology, had made an^ attack^ in^1912 on^ what^ he^ considered

the fundamental scientific assumption^ of^ his^ day,^ that^ scientific^ method^ must

be analytic. He argued that^ the^ scientists^ should^ not^ proceed^ by^ dividing^ a

whole into its elements, and^ discovering^ the laws^ of the^ elements.^ Instead,^ he

stated:

There are wholes, the behaviour of which is not determined by^ that of^ their^ individual elements, but the part-processes are themselves determined by the intinsic^ nature^ of the whole (Ellis, 1938).

Hence it is useless to study the^ elements,^ since the^ properties^ of^ the^ whole^ are

'emergent' and do not inhere^ in the^ parts.^ The^ organization^ of^ the^ whole^ was

described by the Gestalt school^ in terms^ offield^ forces,^ by^ analogy with^ magnetic

and electrical fields. The^ principle^ of^ Isomorphism^ was^ also^ enunciated,^ that the form of brain^ events^ is similar^ to^ the^ form^ of mental events, and^ should^ be

studied by the same principles.

Gestalt psychology, therefore, implied not only a^ rejection of^ Associationist

psychology, but also of the nineteenth-century theory^ of brain action.^ It^ is

significant that^ Lashley^ advanced only^ psychological^ evidence^ against^ the

doctrine of localization of function-his own experiments, Gestalt^ experiments

on perception, and clinical data. Just as Ferrier^ and^ his^ contemporaries^ had

quite consciously looked in^ the brain^ for the^ structural^ basis^ of^ association,^ so

142

Barbara (^) Tizard

distinct structural unit, because of structural or axonographic characteristics, mediates a distinct function whose nature can be revealed by stimulation, or

the effects of clinical or experimental ablation, or preferably both. The effect of

these two sets of assumptions amounts to an implicit doctrine of psychic centres, the mapping out of psychological entities on the cortex. In other words, Associationism has been discarded in favour oftrait-analysis, but the^ nineteenth- century model of the brain has been retained. Fulton, for example, has argued that the lessening of aggression after cingulectomy reveals the^ localization^ of

'emotional expression' in the 'visceral brain'. Neurosurgeons have attempted to

alter personality in specific ways by lesions of specific parts of^ the^ frontal lobes. This is, however, physiological and psychological evidence that the classical model of the brain as an organ of independent centres controlling different functions is inadequate. Large areas of the brain appear to be implicated in most psychological functions (Meyer, I956; Tizard, 1958). The psychological

entities which have been so readily localized (for example, ability to abstract,

arithmetical ability) probably involve many complex processes which may be

differentially impaired. These changing assumptions should be reflected in the

field of brain physiology, where, as in the past, they can be expected to lead

to new departures in research.

REFERENCES BAIN, A. (^) (i855), The^ Senses and the^ Intellect, London. BIANCHI, L. (1922), The Mechanism of the Brain and the Function^ of^ the Frontal^ Lobes, Edinburgh. BORING, E. G. (1929), A History of Experimental Psychology, New York. BROCA, C. (i86i), Bull. Soc. anat., 2me ser., 6, 330-57. BROWN, C. W. (1942), 'Spinal lesions and distance discrimination', J.^ comp.^ Psychol., 33, 305-14. ELLIS, W. D., ed. (I938), A Source Book of Gestalt Psychology, New York. FERRIER, D. (I876), The Functions of the Brain, London. Ist. ed. FERRIER, D. (I886), The Functions of the Brain. London. 2nd. ed. FINLEY, C. B. (^) (i94i), 'Equivalent losses in accuracy of response after central and after peripheral sense deprivation,'. comp. Neurol., 74, 203-37. FLOURENS, P. (I824), 'Exprimental Researches on the properties and functions of the nervous system in the vertebrate animal'. Trans. Wayne Dennis (I948), Readings in the History of Experimental Psychology. FRANZ, S. I.^ (1907), 'On^ the^ functions^ of^ the^ cerebrum;^ the^ frontal^ lobes',^ Arch.^ Psychol., N.Y., I, I-64. GHISELLI, E. E. (1936), 'The effects of lesions in the spinal cord on the ability of^ the^ rat to discriminate differences in inclined planes', J. comp. Psychol., 22, 319. GOLTZ, F. (I882), Abstract in Brain, 4, (^) 554. HUNTER, W. S. (1930), 'A Consideration of^ Lashley's theory of the^ equipotentiality of cerebral action', J. gen. Psychol. 3, 455-68. JAMES, W. (I89I), The^ Principles of Psychology, London. LASHLEY, K.^ S.^ (I929), Brain^ Mechanisms^ and^ Intelligence,^ Chicago. MEYER, V. (1957), 'Critique of Psychological Approaches to Brain Damage', J. ment.^ Sci., I03, 80-I 0. '

Theories of Brain Localizationfrom Flourens to Lashley MULLER, J. (^) (1838), Elements of Physiology. Trans. W. Baly, London. MUNK, H. (I890), Ueber die Functionen der Grosserhirnrinde. PAVLOV, I. P. (^) (i94i), Lectures on Conditioned (^) Reflexes, vol. II, London. PICKETT, J. M. (1952), 'Non-equipotential cortical function in maze learning', Amer. (^) J. Psychol., 65, 177. RAWSON, N. R. (1927), 'Early Steps in Cerebral localisation', Newcastle med. J. reprint. TIZARD, B. (1958), 'The Psychological Effects of Frontal Lesions,' Acta Psychiat. Neurol. Scand., 33, 232-50. VIRCHOW, R. (^) (I858), Cellular-pathologie, Berlin.

I