Docsity
Docsity

Prepare for your exams
Prepare for your exams

Study with the several resources on Docsity


Earn points to download
Earn points to download

Earn points by helping other students or get them with a premium plan


Guidelines and tips
Guidelines and tips

The Tragedy of the Commons: Population and the Limits of the Earth's Resources, Papers of Earth Sciences

The concept of 'no technical solution problems' and specifically discusses the population problem as a commons dilemma. The author argues that the solution to overpopulation cannot be found through science and technology alone, but rather requires a fundamental extension in morality. The text also touches upon the concept of the tragedy of the commons in relation to pollution and the need for coercive laws or taxing devices to prevent it.

Typology: Papers

Pre 2010

Uploaded on 08/09/2009

koofers-user-a1f
koofers-user-a1f 🇺🇸

10 documents

1 / 6

Toggle sidebar

This page cannot be seen from the preview

Don't miss anything!

bg1
What
Shanl
We
Mam?
The
Tragedy
of
the
Commons
The
population
problem
has
no
technical
solution;
it
requires
a
fundamental
extension
in
morality.
Garrett
Hardin
At
the
end
of
a
thoughtful
article
on
the
future
of
nuclear
war,
Wiesner
and
York
(1)
concluded
that:
"Both
sides
in
the
arms
race
are
...
confronted
by
the
dilemma
of
steadily
increasing
military
power
and
steadily
decreasing
national
security.
It
is
our
considered
profes-
sional
judgment
that
this
dilemma
has
no
technical
solution.
If
the
great
pow-
ers
continue
to
look
for
solutions
in
the
area
of
science
and
technology
only,
the
result
will
be
to
worsen
the
situa-
tion."
I
would
like
to
focus
your
attention
not
on
the
subject
of
the
article
(na-
tional
security
in
a
nuclear
world)
but
on
the
kind
of
conclusion
they
reached,
namely
that
there
is
no
technical
solu-
tion
to
the
problem.
An
implicit
and
almost
universal
assumption
of
discus-
sions
published
in
professional
and
semipopular
scientific
journals
is
that
the
problem
under
discussion
has
a
technical
solution.
A
technical
solution
may
be
defined
as
one
that
requires
a
change
only
in.
the
techniques
of
the
natural
sciences,
demanding
little
or
nothing
in
the
way
of
change
in
human
values
or
ideas
of
morality.
In
our
day
(though
not
in
earlier
times)
technical
solutions
are
always
welcome.
Because
of
previous
failures
in
prophecy,
it
takes
courage
to
assert
that
a
desired
technical
solution
is
not
possible.
Wiesner
and
York
exhibited
this
courage;
publishing
in
a
science
journal,
they
insisted
that
the
solution
to
the
problem
was
not
to
be
found
in
the
natural
sciences.
They
cautiously
qualified
their
statement
with
the
phrase,
"It
is
our
considered
profes-
The
author
is
professor
of
biology,
University
of
California,
Santa
Barbara.
This
article
is
based
on
a
presidential
address
presented
before
the
meeting
of
the
Pacific
Division
of
the
Ameri-
can
Association
for the
Advancement
of
Science
at
Utah
State
University,
Logan,
25
June
1968.
13
DECEMBER
1968
sional
judgment.
.
.
."
Vhether
they
were
right
or
not
is
not
the
concern
of
the
present
article.
Rather,
the
concern
here
is
with
the
important
concept
of
a
class
of
human
problems
which
can
be
called
"no
technical
solution
problems,"
and,
more
specifically,
with
the
identifi-
cation
and
discussion
of
one
of
these.
It
is
easy
to
show
that
the
class
is
not
a
null
class.
Recall
the
game
of
tick-
tack-toe.
Consider
the
problem,
"How
can
I
win.
the
game
of
tick-tack-toe?"
It
is
well
known
that
I
cannot,
if
I
as-
sume
(in
keeping
with
the
conventions
of
game
theory)
that
my
opponent
un-
derstands
the
game
perfectly.
Put
an-
other
way,
there
is
no
"technical
solu-
tion"
to
the
problem.
I
can
win
only
by
giving
a
radical
meaning
to
the
word
"win."
I
can
hit
my
opponent
over
the
head;
or
I
can
drug
him;
or
I
can
falsify
the
records.
Every
way
in
which
I
"win"
involves,
in
some
sense,
an
abandon-
ment
of
the
game,
as
we
intuitively
un-
derstand
it.
(I
can
also,
of
course,
openly
abandon
the
game-refuse
to
play
it.
This
is
what
most
adults
do.)
The
class
of
"No
technical
solution
problems"
has
members.
My
thesis
is
that
the
"population
problem,"
as
con-
ventionally
conceived,
is
a
member
of
this
class.
How
it
is
conventionally
con-
ceived
needs
some
comment.
It
is
fair
to
say
that
most
people
who'
anguish
over
the
population
problem
are
trying
to
find
a
way
to
avoid
the
evils
of
over-
population
without
relinquishing
any
of
the
privileges
they
now
enjoy.
They
think
that
farming
the
seas
or
develop-
ing
new
strains
of
wheat
will
solve
the
problem-technologically.
I
try
to
show
here
that
the
solution
they
seek
cannot
be
found.
The
population
problem
can-
not
be
solved
in
a
technical
way,
any
more
than
can
the
problem
of
winning
the
game
of
tick-tack-toe.
Population,
as
Malthus
said,
naturally
tends
to
grow
"geometrically,"
or,
as
we
would
now
say,
exponentially.
In
a
finite
world
this
means
that
the
per
capita
share
of
the
world's
goods
must
steadily
decrease.
Is
ours
a
finite
world?
A
fair
defense
can
be
put
forward
for
the
view
that
the
world
is
infinite;
or
that
we
do
not
know
that
it
is
not.
But,
in
terms
of
the
practical
problems
that
we
must
face
in
the
next
few
genera-
tions
with
the
foreseeable
technology,
it
is
clear
that
we
will
greatly
increase
human
misery
if
we
do
not,
during
the
immediate
future,
assume
that
the
world
available
to
the
terrestrial
human
pop-
ulation
is
finite.
"Space"
is
no
escape
(2).
A
finite
world
can
support
only
a
finite
population;
therefore,
population
growth
must
eventually
equal
zero.
(The
case
of
perpetual
wide
fluctuations
above
and
below
zero
is
a
trivial
variant
that
need
not
be
discussed.)
When
this
condition
is
met,
what
will
be
the
situa-
tion
of
mankind?
Specifically,
can
Ben-
tham's
goal
of
"the
greatest
good
for
the
greatest
number"
be
realized?
No-for
two
reasons,
each
sufficient
by
itself.
The
first
is
a
theoretical
one.
It
is
not
mathematically
possible
to
maximize
for
two
(or
more)
variables
at
the
same
time.
This
was
clearly
stated
by
von
Neumann
and
Morgenstern
(3),
but
the
principle
is
implicit
in
the
theory
of
partial
differential
equations,
dating
back
at
least
to
D'Alembert
(1717-
1783).
The
second
reason
springs
directly
from
biological
facts.
To
live,
any
organism
must
have
a
source
of
energy
(for
example,
food).
This
energy
is
utilized
for
two
puposes:
mere
main-
tenance
and
work.
For
man,
mainte-
nance
of
life
requires
about
1600
kilo-
calories
a
day
("maintenance
calories').
Anything
that
he
does
over
and
above
merely
staying
alive
will
be
defined
as
work,
and
is
supported
by
"work
cal-
ories"
which
he
takes
in.
Work
calories
are
used
not
only
for
what
we
call
work
in
common
speech;
they
are
also
re-
quired
for
all
forms
of
enjoyment,
from
swimming
and
automobile
racing
to
playing
music
and
writing
poetry.
If
our
goal
is
to
maximize
population
it
is
obvious
what
we
must
do:
We
must
make
the
work
calories
per
person
ap-
proach
as
close
to
zero
as
possible.
No
gourmet
meals,
no
vacations,
no
sports,
no
music,
no
literature,
no
art.
. .
.
I
think
that
everyone
will
grant,
without
1243
on January 27, 2009 www.sciencemag.orgDownloaded from
pf3
pf4
pf5

Partial preview of the text

Download The Tragedy of the Commons: Population and the Limits of the Earth's Resources and more Papers Earth Sciences in PDF only on Docsity!

What Shanl We Mam?

The Tragedy of the Commons

The population problem has no technical solution;

it requires a fundamental extension in morality.

Garrett Hardin

At the end of a thoughtful article on

the future of nuclear war, Wiesner and

York (1) concluded that: "Both sides in

the arms race are ... confronted by the

dilemma of steadily increasing military

power and steadily decreasing national

security. It is our considered profes-

sional judgment that this dilemma has

no technical solution. If the great pow-

ers continue to look for solutions in

the area of science and technology only,

the result will be to worsen the situa-

tion."

I would like to focus your attention

not on the subject of the article (na-

tional security in a nuclear world) but

on the kind of conclusion they reached,

namely that there is no technical solu-

tion to the problem. An implicit and

almost universal assumption of discus-

sions published in professional and

semipopular scientific journals is that

the problem under discussion has a

technical solution. A technical solution

may be^ defined as one that requires a

change only in. the techniques of the

natural sciences, demanding little or

nothing in the way of change in human

values or ideas of morality.

In our day (though not in earlier

times) technical solutions are always

welcome. Because of previous failures

in prophecy, it takes courage to assert

that a desired technical solution is not

possible. Wiesner and York exhibited

this courage; publishing in a science

journal, they insisted that the solution

to the problem was not to be found in

the natural sciences. They cautiously

qualified their statement with the

phrase, "It is our considered profes-

The author is professor of biology, University of (^) California, Santa Barbara. This (^) article is based on a presidential address (^) presented before the (^) meeting of the Pacific Division of the (^) Ameri- can Association for the Advancement (^) of Science at Utah State (^) University, Logan, 25 June 1968.

13 DECEMBER 1968

sional judgment... ." Vhether they

were right or not is not the concern of

the present article. Rather, the concern

here is with the important concept of a

class of human problems which can be

called "no technical solution problems,"

and, more specifically, with the identifi-

cation and discussion of one of these.

It is (^) easy to show that the class is not a null class. Recall the game of tick-

tack-toe. Consider the problem, "How

can I win. the game of tick-tack-toe?"

It is well known that I cannot, if I as-

sume (in keeping with the conventions

of game theory) that my opponent (^) un-

derstands the game perfectly. Put an-

other way, there is (^) no "technical solu-

tion" to the problem. I can win only

by giving a^ radical meaning to the word

"win." (^) I can hit my opponent over the

head; or I can drug him; or I can falsify

the records. Every way in which I "win"

involves, in some sense, an abandon-

ment of the game, as we intuitively un-

derstand it. (I can also, of course,

openly abandon the game-refuse to

play it. This is what most adults do.)

The class (^) of "No technical solution

problems" has members. My thesis is

that the "population problem," as con-

ventionally conceived, is a member of

this class. How it is conventionally con-

ceived needs some comment. It is fair

to say that most people who' anguish

over the population problem are trying

to find a way to avoid the evils of over-

population without relinquishing any of

the privileges they now enjoy. They

think that farming the seas or develop-

ing new strains of wheat will solve the

problem-technologically. I try to show

here that the solution they seek cannot

be found. The population problem can-

not be solved in a technical way, any

more than can the problem of winning

the game of tick-tack-toe.

Population, as^ Malthus^ said,^ naturally

tends to grow "geometrically," or, as we

would now say, exponentially. In a

finite world this means that the per

capita share^ of^ the^ world's^ goods must

steadily decrease.^ Is^ ours^ a^ finite^ world?

A fair defense can be put forward for

the view that the world is infinite; or

that we do not know that it is not. But,

in terms of the practical problems that

we must face in the next few genera-

tions with the foreseeable technology, it

is clear that we will greatly increase

human misery if we do not, during the

immediate future, assume that the world

available to the terrestrial human pop-

ulation is finite. "Space" is no escape

A finite world can support only a

finite population; therefore, population

growth must^ eventually equal zero.^ (The

case of perpetual wide fluctuations

above and below zero is a (^) trivial variant

that need not be discussed.) When this

condition is met, what will be the situa-

tion of mankind? Specifically, can Ben-

tham's goal of "the greatest good for

the greatest number" be realized?

No-for two reasons, each sufficient

by itself. The^ first^ is^ a^ theoretical one.

It is not mathematically possible to

maximize for two (or more) variables at

the same time. This was clearly stated

by von^ Neumann^ and^ Morgenstern (3),

but the principle is implicit in the theory

of partial differential equations, dating

back at least to D'Alembert (1717-

The second reason springs directly

from biological facts. To live, any

organism must^ have^ a^ source^ of^ energy

(for example, food). This^ energy is

utilized for two puposes: mere main-

tenance and work. For man, mainte-

nance of life requires about 1600 kilo-

calories a day ("maintenance calories').

Anything that^ he does^ over^ and^ above

merely staying alive^ will be^ defined as

work, and is^ supported by "work cal-

ories" which he takes in. Work calories

are used not only for what we call work

in common speech; they are also re-

quired for^ all^ forms^ of^ enjoyment, from

swimming and automobile racing to

playing music^ and^ writing poetry. If

our goal is to maximize population it is

obvious what we must do: We must

make the work calories per person ap-

proach as^ close^ to^ zero as possible. No

gourmet meals, no vacations, no sports,

no music, no literature, no art.... I

think that everyone will grant, without

argument or proof, that maximizing

population does not max2imize goods.

Bentham's goal is impossible.

In reaching this conclusion I have

made the usual assumption that it is

the acquisition of energy that is the

problem. The appearance of atomic energy has led some to question this assumption. However, given an infinite source of energy, population growth

still produces an inescapable problem.

The problem of the acquisition of en-

ergy is replaced by the problem of its

dissipation, as J. H. Fremlin has so wit-

tily shown (4). The arithmetic signs in

-t-he analysis are, as it were, reversed;

but Bentham's goal is still unobtainable.

The optimum population is, then, less

than the maximum. The difficulty of

defining the optimum is enormous; so

far as I know, no one has seriously

tackled this problem. Reaching an ac-

ceptable and stable solution will surely

require more than one generation of

hard analytical work-and much per-

suasion.

We want the maximum good per

person; but what is good? To one per-

son it is wilderness, to another it is ski

lodges for^ thousands. To one it is estu-

aries to nourish ducks for hunters^ to

shoot; to another it is factory land.

Comparing one good with another is,

we usually say, impossible because

goods are incommensurable. Incommen-

surables cannot be compared.

Theoretically this may be true; but in

real life incommensurables are commen-

surable. Only a^ criterion of^ judgment

and a system of weighting are^ needed.

In nature the criterion is survival. Is it

better for a species to be small and hide-

able, or large and powerful? Natural

selection commensurates the incommen-

surables. The compromise achieved de-

pends on a natural weighting of the

values of the variables.

Man must imitate this process. There

is no doubt that in fact he already does,

but unconsciously. It is when the hidden

decisions are made explicit that the

arguments begin. The problem for the

years ahead is to work out an accept-

able theory of weighting. Synergistic

effects, nonlinear variation, and difficul-

ties in discounting the future make the

intellectual problem difficult, but^ not

(in principle) insoluble.

Has any cultural group solved^ this

practical problem at the^ present time,

even on an^ intuitive level? One^ simple

fact proves that^ none^ has:^ there is^ no

prosperous population in^ the^ world^ to-

day that has, and has^ had for^ some

time,-p - rate of zero. Any people

that has intuitively identified its opti-

mum point will soon reach it, after

which its growth rate becomes and re-

mains zero.

Of course, a positive growth rate

might be taken as evidence that a pop-

ulation is below its optimum. However,

by any reasonable standards, the most

rapidly growing populations on earth

today are (in general) the most misera-

ble. This association (which need not be

invariable) casts doubt on the optimistic

assumption that the positive growth rate

of a population is evidence that it has

yet to reach its optimum.

We can make little progress in work-

ing toward optimum poulation size until

we explicitly exorcize the spirit of

Adam Smith in the field of practical

demography. In economic affairs, The

Wealth of Nations (1776) popularized

the "invisible hand," the idea that an

individual who "intends only his own

gain," is, as it were, "led by an invisible

hand to promote. (^) .,. the public interest"

(5). Adam Smith did not assert that

this was invariably true, and perhaps

neither did any of his followers. But he

contributed to a dominant tendency of

thought that has ever since interfered

with positive action based on rational

analysis, namely, the tendency to as-

sume that decisions reached individually

will, in fact, be the best decisions for an

entire society. If this assumption is

correct it justifies the continuance of

our present policy of laissez-faire in

reproduction. If it is correct we can as-

sume that men will control their individ-

ual fecundity so as to produce the opti-

mum population. If the assumption is

not correct, we need to reexamine our

individual freedoms to see which ones are defensible.

Tragedy of Freedom in a Commons

The rebuttal to the invisible hand in

population control^ is^ to^ be^ found in^ a

scenario first sketched in a little-known

pamphlet (6) in 1833 by a mathematical

amateur named William Forster Lloyd

(1794-1852). We may well call it^ "the

tragedy of the commons," using the

word "tragedy" as the philosopher

Whitehead used it (7): "The^ essence^ of

dramatic tragedy is^ not^ unhappiness. It

resides in the solemnity of the^ remorse-

less working of things." He^ then'^ goes on.

to say, "This^ inevitableness^ of^ destiny

can only be^ illustrated^ in^ terms^ of hu-

man life by incidents which in fact in-

volve unhappiness. For it is only by

them that the futility of escape can be

made evident in the drama."

The tragedy of the commons develops

in this way. Picture a pasture open to

all. It is to be expected that each herds-

man will try to keep as many cattle as

possible on the commons.^ Such^ an ar-

rangement may work reasonably satis-

factorily for centuries because tribal

wars, poaching, and disease keep the

numbers of both man and beast well

below the carrying capacity of the land.

Finally, however, comes the day of

reckoning, that is, the^ day when the

long-desired goal of social stability be-

comes a reality. At this point, the in-

herent logic of the commons remorse-

lessly generates tragedy.

As a rational being, each herdsman

seeks to maximize his gain. Explicitly

or implicitly, more or less consciously,

he asks, "What is the utility to me of

adding one more animal to my herd?"

This utility has one negative and one

positive component.

  1. The positive component is a func-

tion of the increment of one animal.

Since the herdsman receives all the

proceeds from the sale of the additional

animal, the positive utility is nearly +1.

2) The negative component is a func-

tion of^ the^ additional^ overgrazing

created by one^ more^ animal.^ Since,

however, the effects^ of^ overgrazing are

shared by all the herdsmen, the^ negative

utility for any particular decision-

making herdsman is only a^ fraction^ of

Adding together the component par-

tial utilities, the rational herdsman

concludes that the only sensible course

for him to pursue is to add another

animal to his herd. And^ another; and

another.... But this is the conclusion

reached by each and^ every rational

herdsman sharing a^ commons.^ Therein

is the tragedy. Each man is locked into

a system that compels him to^ increase

his herd without limit-in^ a^ world^ that

is limited. Ruin is^ the destination^ to-

ward which^ all^ men^ rush, each^ pursuing

his own best interest in a society that

believes in the freedom of the com-

mons. Freedom in a commons brings

ruin to all.

Some would say that this^ is^ a^ plati-

tude. Would that it^ were!^ In^ a^ sense, it

was learned thousands of^ years ago, but

natural selection favors^ the forces of

psychological denial^ (8). The individual

benefits as an^ individual^ from^ his^ ability

to deny the truth^ even^ though society as

a whole, of which he is a part, suffers.

SCIENCE, VOL. 162

watch the watchers themselves?" John

Adams said that we must have "a gov-

ernment of laws and not men." Bureau

administrators, trying to evaluate the morality (^) of acts in the total system, are

singularly liable to corruption, produc-

ing a government by men, not laws.

Prohibition is easy to legislate

(though not necessarily to enforce); but

how do we legislate temperance? Ex-

perience indicates that it can be ac-

complished best through the mediation of administrative law. We limit possi-

bilities unnecessarily if we suppose that

the sentiment of Quis custodiet denies

us the use of administrative law. We should rather retain the phrase as a perpetual reminder of fearful dangers we cannot avoid. The great challenge

facing us now is to invent the corrective

feedbacks that are needed to keep cus-

todians honest. We must find ways to

legitimate the needed authority of both

the (^) custodians and the corrective feed-

backs.

Freedom To Breed Is Intolerable

The tragedy of the commons is in-

volved in population problems in an-

other way. In a world governed solely

by the principle of "dog eat dog"-if

indeed there ever was such a world-

how many children a family had would

not be a matter of public concern.

Parents who bred too exuberantly would

leave fewer descendants, not more, be-

cause they would be unable to care

adequately for their children. David

Lack and others have found that such a

negative feedback demonstrably con-

trols the fecundity of birds (11). But

men are not birds, and have not acted

like them for millenniums, at least.

If each human family were depen-

dent only on its own resources; if the

children of improvident parents starved

to death; if, thus, overbreeding brought

its own "punishment" to the germ line-

then there would be no public interest

in controlling the breeding of families.

But our society is deeply committed to

the welfare state (12), and hence is

confronted with another aspect of the

tragedy of^ the^ commons.

In a welfare state, how shall we deal

with the family, the religion, the race,

or the class (or indeed any distinguish-

able and cohesive group) that adopts

overbreeding as^ a^ policy to^ secure^ its

own aggrandizement (13)? To couple

the concept of^ freedom^ to^ breed with

the belief that everyone born has an

equal right to the commons is to (^) lock the world into a tragic course of action. Unfortunately this is just the course of action that is being pursued by the United Nations. In late 1967, some 30 nations agreed to the following (14): The Universal Declaration of (^) Human Rights describes the family as the natural and fundamental unit of society. It fol- lows that any choice and decision with regard to the size of the family must irte- vocably rest with the family itself, and cannot be made by anyone else. It is painful to have to deny (^) categor- ically the validity of this right; denying

it, one feels as uncomfortable as a resi-

dent of Salem, Massachusetts, who

denied the reality of witches in the 17th century. At the present time, in liberal quarters, something like a taboo acts to

inhibit criticism of the United Nations.

There is a feeling that the United

Nations is "our last and best hope,"

that we shouldn't find fault with it; we

shouldn't play into the hands of the

archconservatives. However, let us not

forget what Robert Louis Stevenson

said: "The truth that is suppressed by

friends is the readiest weapon of the

enemy." If we love the truth we must

openly deny the validity of the Universal

Declaration of Human Rights, even

though it is promoted by the United

Nations. We should also join with

Kingsley Davis (15) in attempting to

get Planned Parenthood-World Popula-

tion to see the error of its ways in em-

bracing the same tragic ideal.

Conscience Is Self-Eliminating

It is a mistake to think that we can

control the breeding of mankind in the

long run by an appeal to conscience.

Charles Galton Darwin made this point

when he spoke on the centennial of the

publication of his grandfather's great

book. The argument is straightforward

and Darwinian.

People vary. Confronted with^ appeals

to limit breeding, some people will un-

doubtedly respond to^ the^ plea more

than others. Those who have more

children will produce a larger fraction

of the next generation than those with

more susceptible consciences. The dif-

ference will be accentuated, generation

by generation.

In C. G. Darwin's words: "It may

well be that it would take hundreds of

generations for the progenitive instinct

to develop in this way, but if it should

do so, nature would^ have^ taken her

revenge, and the^ variety Homo^ contra-

cipiens would become extinct and

would be replaced by the variety Homo

progenitivus" (16).

The argument assumes that con-

science or the desire for children (no

matter which) is hereditary-but heredi-

tary only in^ the^ most^ general formal

sense. The^ result will^ be^ the same

whether the attitude is transmitted

through germ cells, or exosomatically,

to use A. J. Lotka's term. (If one denies

the latter possibility as well as the

former, then what's the point of educa-

tion?) The argument has here been

stated in the context of the population

problem, but it applies equally well to

any instance in which society appeals

to an individual exploiting a commons to restrain (^) himself for the general

good-by means^ of his conscience. To

make such an appeal is to set up a

selective system that works toward the elimination of conscience from the race.

Pathogenic Effects of Conscience

The long-term disadvantage of an

appeal to conscience should be enough

to condemn it; but has serious short-

term disadvantages as well. If we ask

a man who is exploiting a commons to

desist "in the name of conscience,"

what are we saying to him? What does

he hear?-not only at the moment but

also in the wee small hours of the

night when, half^ asleep, he remembers

not merely the words we used but also the nonverbal communication cues we gave him unawares? Sooner or later,

consciously or subconsciously, he senses

that he has received two communica-

tions, and that they are contradictory:

(i) (intended communication) "If^ you

don't do as we ask, we will openly con-

demn you for not acting like^ a respon-

sible citizen"; (ii) (the unintended

communication) "If you do behave as

we ask, we will secretly condemr. you

for a simpleton who can be shamed

into standing aside while the rest of us

exploit the commons."

Everyman then is caught in what

Bateson has called a "double bind." Bateson (^) and his co-workers have made

a plausible case for viewing the double

bind as an important causative factor in

the genesis of schizophrenia (17). The

double bind may not always be so

damaging, but^ it^ always endangers the

mental health of (^) anyone to whom it is

applied. "A bad conscience," said

Nietzsche, "is a kind of illness."

To conjure up a conscience in others

SCIENCE, VOL. 162

is tempting to anyone who wishes to

extend his control beyond the legal

limits. Leaders at the highest level

succumb to this temptation. Has^ any

President during the past generation

failed to call on labor unions to moder-

ate voluntarily their demands for higher

wages, or to steel companies to honor

voluntary guidelines on prices? I can

recall none. The rhetoric used on such

occasions is designed to produce feel-

ings of guilt in noncooperators.

For centuries it was assumed without

proof that guilt was a valuable, perhaps

even an indispensable, ingredient of the

civilized life. Now, in this post-Freudian

world, we doubt it. Paul Goodman (^) speaks from the modern point (^) of view when he says:

"No good has ever come from feeling

guilty, neither intelligence, policy, nor

compassion. The guilty do not pay

attention to the object but only to them-

selves, and not even to their own in-

terests, which might make sense, but to

their anxieties" (18).

One does not have to be a profes-

sional psychiatrist to see the conse-

quences of anxiety. We in the Western

world are just emerging from a dreadful

two-centuries-long Dark Ages of Eros

that was sustained partly by prohibi-

tion laws, but perhaps more effectively

by the anxiety-generating mechanisms

of (^) education. Alex Comfort has told the

story well in The Anxiety Makers (19);

it is not a pretty one.

Since proof is difficult, we may even

concede that the results of anxiety may

sometimes, from certain points of view,

be desirable. The larger question we

should ask is whether, as a matter of

policy, we should ever encourage the

use of a (^) technique the tendency (if not

the intention) of which is psycholog-

ically pathogenic. We hear much talk

these days of responsible parenthood;

the coupled words are incorporated

into the titles of some organizations de-

voted to birth control. Some people

have proposed massive propaganda

campaigns to instill responsibility into

the nation's (or the world's) breeders.

But what is the meaning of the word

responsibility in this context? Is it not

merely a synonym for the word con-

science? When we use the word re-

sponsibility in the absence of substantial

sanctions are we not trying to browbeat

a free man in a commons into acting

against his own interest? Responsibility

is a verbal counterfeit for a substantial

quid pro quo. It is an attempt to get

something for nothing.

13 DECEMBER 1968

If the word responsibility is to be

used at all, I suggest that it be in the

sense Charles Frankel uses it (20).

"Responsibility," says this philosopher,

"is the product of definite social ar-

rangements." Notice that Frankel calls

for social arrangements-not propa-

ganda.

Mutual Coercion

Mutually Agreed upon

The social arrangements that produce

responsibility are arrangements that

create coercion, of some sort. Consid-

er bank-robbing. The man who takes

money from a bank acts as if the bank

were a commons. How do we prevent

such action? Certainly not by trying to

control his behavior solely by a verbal

appeal to his sense of responsibility.

Rather than rely on propaganda we

follow Frankel's lead and insist that a bank (^) is not a commons; we seek the definite social arrangements that will

keep it from becoming a commons.

That we thereby infringe on the free-

dom of would-be robbers we neither

deny nor^ regret.

The morality of bank-robbing is

particularly easy to understand because

we accept complete prohibition of this

activity. We are willing to say "Thou

shalt not rob banks," without providing

for exceptions. But temperance also can

be created by coercion. Taxing is a good

coercive device. To keep downtown

shoppers temperate in their use of

parking space we introduce parking

meters for short periods, and traffic

fines for longer ones. We need not

actually forbid a citizen to park as long

as he wants to; we need merely make it

increasingly expensive for him to do so.

Not prohibition, but carefully biased

options are what we offer him. A Madi-

son Avenue man might call this per-

suasion; I prefer the greater candor of

the word coercion.

Coercion is a dirty word to most

liberals now, but it need not forever be

so. As with the four-letter words, its

dirtiness can be cleansed away by ex-

posure to the light, by saying it over and

over without apology or embarrassment.

To many, the word (^) coercion implies

arbitrary decisions of distant and irre-

sponsible bureaucrats; but this is not a

necessary part of its meaning. The only

kind of coercion I recommend is mutual

coercion, mutually agreed upon by the

majority of the people affected.

To say that we (^) mutually agree to

coercion is not to say that we are re-

quired to^ enjoy it, or^ even^ to^ pretend

we enjoy it. Who enjoys taxes? We all

grumble about^ them.^ But^ we accept

compulsory taxes^ because^ we^ recognize

that voluntary taxes would favor the

conscienceless. We institute and (grum-

blingly) support taxes^ and^ other^ coercive

devices to escape the horror of the

commons.

An alternative to the commons need

not be perfectly just to be preferable.

With real estate and (^) other material

goods, the^ alternative^ we^ have chosen

is the institution of private property

coupled with^ legal inheritance.^ Is this

system perfectly just? As^ a^ genetically

trained biologist I deny that it is. It

seems to me that, if there are to be dif-

ferences in individual inheritance, legal

possession should^ be^ perfectly cor-

related with biological inheritance-that

those who are biologically more fit to

be the custodians of property and (^) power

should legally inherit more. But genetic

recombination continually makes a

mockery of^ the^ doctrine^ of^ "like^ father,

like son" implicit in our laws of legal in-

heritance. An idiot can inherit millions,

and a trust fund can keep his estate

intact. We must admit that our legal

system of^ private property plus inheri-

tance is unjust-but we put up with it

because we are not convinced, at the

moment, that anyone has invented a

better system. The alternative of the

commons is too horrifying to contem-

plate. Injustice is^ preferable to total

ruin.

It is one of the peculiarities of the

warfare between reform and the status

quo that it is thoughtlessly governed

by a^ double^ standard.^ Whenever a re-

form measure is proposed it is often

defeated when its opponents trium-

phantly discover a flaw in it. As Kings-

ley Davis has^ pointed out^ (21), worship-

pers of the status quo sometimes imply

that no reform is possible without unan-

imous agreement, an implication con-

trary to historical fact. As nearly as I

can make out, automatic rejection of

proposed reforms is based on one of

two unconscious assumptions: (i) that

the status quo is perfect; or (ii) that the

choice we face is between reform and

no action; if the proposed reform is

imperfect, we presumably should take

no action at all, while we wait for a

perfect proposal.

But we can never do nothing. That

which we have done for thousands of

years is also action. It also produces

evils. Once we are aware that the