









Study with the several resources on Docsity
Earn points by helping other students or get them with a premium plan
Prepare for your exams
Study with the several resources on Docsity
Earn points to download
Earn points by helping other students or get them with a premium plan
Community
Ask the community for help and clear up your study doubts
Discover the best universities in your country according to Docsity users
Free resources
Download our free guides on studying techniques, anxiety management strategies, and thesis advice from Docsity tutors
The Gettier Problem, a counterexample to the Justified True Belief (JTB) theory of knowledge. The author examines the conditions under which someone can be said to know that something is the case, and argues that having adequate evidence for a belief does not necessarily mean that one knows that something is true. The document also explores the implications of this problem for the demands of inquiry and the limitations of epistemic titles.
Typology: Lecture notes
1 / 15
This page cannot be seen from the preview
Don't miss anything!
teorema Vol. XXVIII/3, 2009, pp. 49- [ BIBLID 0210-1602 (2009) 28:3; pp. 49-63]
RESUMEN En este trabajo se analiza el Problema de Gettier y se llama la atención sobre el papel que juegan ciertos principios de inferencia en la construcción de contraejemplos al análisis clásico del saber como creencia verdadera y justificada. Se argumenta que el uso que se hace de esos principios en esa construcción es inapropiado. Ello se debe a que para rechazar este análisis se conciben los principios de la inferencia lógica co- mo si fuesen independientes de cómo se conduce la búsqueda del saber y como si su validez se estableciera a priori. En contra de esto se señala que, desde un punto de vista pragmatista, esos principios son el destilado de la práctica de la investigación y del acopio de garantías epistémicas competentes. Finalmente, se subraya la afinidad de este diagnóstico con ciertas ideas de Dewey sobre la naturaleza de las verdades ló- gicas y de Dretske acerca de por qué ni el saber ni los avales epistémicos están cerra- dos por la relación de consecuencia lógica.
PALABRAS CLAVE: Problema de Gettier, garantía epistémica, inferencia lógica, inves- tigación, pragmatismo.
ABSTRACT In this paper the Gettier Problem is approached by calling attention to the role played by certain principles of inference that are used to provide counterexamples to the classical analysis of knowledge as justified true belief — the JTB-analysis. It is argued that the use to which those principles are put in such a task is inappropriate. In order to object to the JTB-analysis, the principles are conceived of as independent of the way the search for knowledge is conducted and as valid a priori. As against this and from a Pragmatist stance, the principles are distilled within the practice of skilled inquiry and within the gathering of epistemic warrant. Finally, this explanation of why Gettier’s attack on the JTB-analysis fails is shown to be akin to Dewey’s views of the nature of logical truths and to Drestke’s arguments of why neither knowledge nor epistemic warrants are closed under logical entailment.
KEYWORDS : Gettier Problem Epistemic Entitlement, Logical Inference, Inquiry, Pragmatism.
50 Juan José Acero
My aim in this paper is to pave the way for an answer to the question as to how the well-known Gettier Problem arises for the analysis of knowledge as justified true belief [= JTB]. What is specific about such an answer is that it calls attention to the role played by certain principles of logic in demolish- ing the JTB-analysis. The idea is that unless you approve of applying those principles and ground such approval on proper reasons, the JTB-analysis is not put on the ropes. Although the decision to suspend the application of those principles does not fit in with the generally assumed unrestricted valid- ity of principles of logic, it is not something unexpected from the point of view of a pragmatist view of knowledge and epistemic justification. If the principles of logic are not enforced from without, but are precipitates of hu- man inquiry, something John Dewey made much of, then they are not beyond the demands imposed by inquiry’s specific problems and constraints.
Here is a typical way of gettiering the JTB-analysis.^1 (A definition is gettiered, if a case is arranged which literally satisfies the definiens condi- tions in spite of its visibly betraying the definiens ’ spirit.) First, we define knowledge in the usual way:
(1) S knows that α iff (i) S believes that α, (ii) it is true that α, and (iii) S is completely justified in believing that α.
Let us accept now that conditions (i) and (iii) in (1) are fulfilled, that is, S be- lieves that a is P and is completely justified in believing that a is P. That is, both
(2) S believes that a is P
and
(3) S is completely justified in believing that a is P
are true. (Instead of saying that S is completely justified in believing that a is P , I will say that S has adequate evidence that a is P , or that S is entitled to think that a is P.) Now, since the proposition that something is P follows from the proposition that a is P , it seems that we could infer (4) from (2) and (5) from (3):
52 Juan José Acero
S has adequate evidence. Drop (3) and you avoid taking the step that leads to (5), a step that creates the conditions for S to be lucky enough to gain the right entitlement. I share much of this view, but it could be pointed out that, regardless of S ’s scrupulousness as an evidence-gatherer, giving up (3) is too harsh a measure. As soon as one agrees to this judgement, it becomes natural to think of the rule of existential generalization as the key element in the tran- sition from (3) to (5). In order to avoid reaching the wrong conclusion, i.e., that S knows that something is P (that I know that some student of mine owns a Ford), I suggest that we do not accept that S ’s evidence to think that a is P is closed under known entailment. In other words, that by adding to the fact that S is entitled to assert that a is P the fact that something’s being P logi- cally follows from a ’s being P — and that S knows it as well — you have still won the right to assert that S is entitled to assert that something is P. S could be completely justified in believing that a is P and could be completely justified in believing that if a is P , then something is P ; however, it does not follow from these premises that S could be completely justified in believing that something is P. Thus, (5) is false. Justified belief, warrant, and epistemic entitlement are not closed under existential generalization. (I come back to this below.) To generalize, entitlements are not closed under logical implication. This analysis is not ad hoc. Another well-known Gettier manoeuvre puts the JTB-analysis on the ropes by exploiting the principle of logic that supports us in inferring (8) from (3):
(8) S is completely justified in believing that ( a is P or that b is P ).
If instead of (7) we accept the truth of (9)
(9) b is P
another Gettier cul-de-sac is reached, one which runs parallel to that put for- ward above. The principle of logic now involved is that which allows infer- ring from any proposition α the proposition (α ∨ β). Since two coincidences might be too many in this context, I choose to agree that S is completely justi- fied in believing that a is P and recommend we reject that S is completely justified in believing that something is P. Is there a way out of Gettier’s laby- rinth that could somehow be backed by argument and not remain ad hoc?
Let us go back to (3). S is completely justified in believing that a is P. S has adequate evidence, warrants, to think that a is P , has won a title to assert that a is P. In order to gain such a title, S must have inquired into a ’s envi-
The Gettier Problem and the Demands of Inquiry 53
ronment, followed a ’s tracks and examined a ’s features and relations. Finally, S concludes that a is P. I will say that the evidence S has gathered and arranged as to what a is like bears the watermark or is -watermarked , because the title S has is a title of a. (We may pretend that any inquiry into what an in- dividual x is like becomes materialized in a < x >-watermarked medium.) It is interesting to realize that while S ’s title is < a >-watermarked, any title — not necessarily one gained by S — that certifies that something is P need not be < a >-watermarked. Maybe S has been told that something is P without being informed who or what is P! However, with a view to keeping myself within the terms in which Gettier Problems are usually discussed, I shall concede that S ’s title that something is P , i.e., the (Something is P )-title, obtains its validity from the title that guarantees that a is P — one that is < a >- watermarked. Because of it, I will assume that the (Something is P )-title is < a >-watermarked as well. The tricky ingredient in the Gettier Problem comes on stage with (7). It is said that something is P , but any inquiry’s results that undermine S ’s evidence either become embodied in a title with no watermark at all or become embodied in a < b >-watermarked title, for a ≠ b. If (7) has to play a central role in defeating S’s (Something is P)-title, not a ’s life, envi- ronment, behaviour, and so on, but something else’s — b , c or whoever he or she is — has to be inquired into. This is what Gettier and, I suspect, anyone who shares Gettier’s strategy have overlooked. In order for anyone to under- mine the JTB-analysis, in inferring (5) from (3) the premise’s watermark has simply to be ignored or removed. In other words, the principle of existential generalization has to be so understood that the ‘Something is P ’ that figures in (5) and the ‘Something is P ’ that figures in (7) become backed by the same titles.^2 And once the same content with the same epistemic support is used to index S ’s epistemic warrant, the claim that S knows that something is P , i.e., that S knows (7), loses any foundations it could have had. What one cannot lose sight of is that the principle of existential generalization has been bent to force S’s title to contradict the facts. If this principle should transfer the premise’s watermarks to its conclusion, there would be no possibility of equivocating on ‘Something is P ’, and then the Gettier Problem would not arise. Provided that this requirement has not been satisfied, the so-called Get- tier cases are an artefact of a dubious way of conceiving the demands of cer- tain principles of logic on us.^3
A variant of this analysis of Gettier cases introduces a time parameter in S ’s evidence. It could happen that S has gained the right to assert that a is P at t (or up to t ). S ’s title to say so is not only -watermarked but dated at t (al- ternatively, t-dated ) as well. Such a title’s guarantee does not extend beyond
The Gettier Problem and the Demands of Inquiry 55
I will now set forth and comment on some implications of Dewey’s view of logic that sustain the argument deployed in §§ III-V against the at- tempt at gettiering the JTB-analysis. A moment’s reflection is enough to realize that the strategy of deriving the conclusion that S knows that something is P , i.e., that I know that some- one owns a Ford, is openly contrary to how inquiry was conceived by Dewey. (We should not overlook at this point that knowledge is what lies at the end of successful inquiry. For Dewey this is true by definition .) 5 It has to be taken for granted that there is some reason why S gets involved in inquir- ing into whether a is P , but it is never said what reasons push S to do it, what problem S is confronting that could be overcome by discovering whether it is true that a is P. Nor what alternatives to a ’s being P the agent S is weighing up. The only thing we are assured of is that S has somehow managed to ob- tain adequate evidence that a is P. Then, once the derivation’s crucial step has been reached, that evidence is recovered to attribute the (Something is P )- title to S. Nothing warrants this step. The inquiry that S has supposedly car- ried out to conclude that something is P does fulfil those requirements, i.e. being properly watermarked and t -dated, which are built into what it is to gain such an epistemic title. Because of this, S is not in a position to war- rantly assert that something is P. To be in such a position asks for an utterly different scenario from the one pictured by Gettier. In his Logic Dewey does not comment on what role the quantifier ‘something’ plays within inquiry. However, the reader can find some insight- ful remarks concerning the logic of ‘some’ that bear on the problem we are discussing. According to him,
‘Some’ is logically either excessive or deficient. It is excessive, if a singular case has been determined (not in fact an easy matter); it is deficient, if ‘some’ is understood in its strict logical force, namely, as an indication of a possibility, of the form ‘may be’ or ‘perhaps’ [Dewey (1938), p. 195].
The first choice in this alternative, i.e. that ‘some’ is excessive, is unduly ap- pealed to by those who attack the JTB-analysis of knowledge. ‘Unduly’ be- cause nothing in the kind of scenario Gettier pictures makes S an inquirer who earns the right to warrantly assert, i.e. to know, that something is P. As I insisted in § III, the Gettier-type scenario is designed so that S is acknowl- edged a title, i.e. the (something is P )-title, the basis of the acknowledgement being that S had already gained another title, i.e. the ( a is P )-title, endowed with the right watermark, namely an < a >-watermark. This watermark is ei- ther put aside or ignored when S is credited with the (something is P )-title. Nothing prevents each different (something is P )-title from carrying its own
56 Juan José Acero
watermarks and further guarantees — a fact that the designer of a Gettier- type scenario exploits by arranging things so that the (something is P )-title that S finally obtains is not < a >-watermarked. On the other hand, S could warrantly assert that something is P , even if this assertion is not the result of an inquiry, concerning one particular individual, that S or someone else suc- cessfully carried out. For instance, I could often find my parking space at the university taken by a Ford and, without having spotted anyone invading it, be led to believe that a student of mine is the Ford’s owner. In so far as I do not know who parks in my place, if I come to think that some one has taken it, ‘some’ cannot but have what Dewey calls the deficient reading, according to which ‘some’ symbolizes a certain stage of inquiry in which a number of relevant questions remain unsettled. This stage is not the basis needed to sup- port a Gettier-type scenario, because the belief that something is P may rep- resent a less advanced stage of the agent’s inquiry than the belief that a is P , and having the evidence that a is P may represent a less advanced stage of evidence gathering than having the evidence that something is P. For the de- fender of the JTB-analysis of knowledge it is possible to get round the Gettier Problem by resorting to Dewey’s two readings of ‘some’ and setting the ap- propriate conditions for inferring that S believes and has adequate evidence that something is P — (4) and (5) above — from S ’s believing that a is P and being completely justified that a is P — (2) and (3) above — respectively. I have not argued that a principle of logic like that of existential gener- alization leads us from true premises to false consequences. Far from it, I have argued that principles of logic can lead from propositions that symbol- ize fruitful inquiry stages to propositions that symbolize idle inquiry stages. And I have also put forward that if those inferential transitions are chal- lenged, the way towards gettiering the JTB-analysis of knowledge is blocked. This very last point of my argument I wish to develop a little more by ad- dressing the following question: Why can an epistemic title that warrants that p as far as a certain inquiry I 1 is concerned not guarantee that q relative to an- other inquiry I 2 , when q logically follows from p? Why can epistemic guaran- tees not be transferred from one title to another unless both of them are adequately related? As an answer I suggest that it is inappropriate to demand that a title that underwrites the right to warrantly assert that p , be valid be- yond the limits for which it was acknowledged. Validity limits matter very much. This is the idea I am going to insist on in what follows. Dewey conceived of inquiry as a process through which one problem- atic situation is transformed into another of a kind he described as deter- mined. He conceived of problem solving within inquiry contexts as the way to turn an initial range of challenging conditions into a new kind of situation in which those former conditions have been replaced by favourable ones. To make such a change possible, both conceptual and material supplies have to be designed and deployed. Among those supplies there will be new hypothe-
58 Juan José Acero
problem at the beginning of the inquiry, i.e. the question to which an answer has to be given:
{What is a like?} a is P , a is Q 1 , a is Q 2, etc.
Further work makes it possible for S to choose one option from those in the contrast class, and the end of the inquiry entitles S to assert that a is P. Since a is the individual who has been checked in order to find out whether he or she is P or Q 1 or Q 2 , etc., the title S is credited with is < a >-watermarked (and t -dated). We know, however, that the Gettier Problem is so designed that this title is worthless and does not warrant S ’s assertion that a is P. On the other hand, the design also requires that something is P and that a more careful in- quiry, though one beyond S ’s calculations, would provide the talented — or maybe the fortunate — seeker with another title, one which would guarantee that someone else, not a but c , is P. In fact, this inquiry is not conducted by anyone. What matters is that unless this condition is fulfilled, there is no Get- tier Problem left at all. As a consequence, no contrast class for such an in- quiry has been fixed and the inquiry’s scope is undetermined. Secondly, to judge S ’s credential to assert that something is P on the basis of S ’s evidence to judge that a is P amounts to changing the problem S is inquiring into. As Dewey suggests when commenting on the deficient use of ‘some’, the con- trast class involved in an inquiry that leads to warrantly assert that something is P is not {What is a like?} but the following:
{Who/what is P ?} a is P , b is P , c is P , etc.
To change the contrast class is to change the problem. By ignoring the differ- ence between these contrast classes we blind ourselves to the demands of in- quiry and unduly extend the worth of epistemic titles beyond their limits.^6
In several papers, and over a long time span, Drestke has argued that knowledge and other epistemic notions are not closed under logical conse- quence and known implication. Thus, even though S knows that p and knows that (if p then q ), S may not know that q. It is also possible that R be reasons that explain why it is the case that p and that p logically implies that q with- out R being reasons that explain why it is the case that q. Moreover, though R is a reason for S to do A and S ’s doing A logically implies S ’s doing B , R may be not a reason for S to do B. Finally, though R would not be the case unless it were the case that p , if p logically implies that q , R and q can be simultane- ously true. Drestke has argued that patterns of inference like these are not
The Gettier Problem and the Demands of Inquiry 59
logically valid. Since his reasons to arrive at such a conclusion seem to me to be sound, my target from now on is to understand why reasons, warrants or titles do not in general transmit their worth to their logical consequences. Let us see two illustrations of this idea to which Drestke repeatedly comes back. We visit the zoo and stop at the zebra’s enclosure. The animals are there in full view. It is entirely natural to claim that we have seen zebras in the zoo; alternatively, that we know that the animals right over there, in the zebra’s enclosure, are zebras, neither gnus nor elephants. In addition to this, we also know that being a zebra logically implies not being cleverly painted mules. However, it is worse than dubious that we know that the animals over there, in the zebra’s enclosure, are not cleverly painted mules. Or think of the fol- lowing variation. First, those animals in the zebra’s enclosure would not be there unless they were zebras. Second, it is logically true that if an animal is a zebra then it is not a cleverly painted mule. However, it is not necessarily true that those animals in the zebra’s enclosure would not be there unless they were not cleverly painted mules. Is there any reason why knowledge, reasons and titles are not closed under logical consequence? Drestke has pointed out two reasons for this. Ac- cording to the most recent, our beliefs’ and judgements’ titles, our supporting reasons, do not transmit their guarantees to their logical consequences. There is nothing in this fact to be astonished at. On the contrary, “[t]he non- transmissibility (to many of the known consequences) of most of our reasons for believing [that] p is an absolutely pervasive phenomenon” [Drestke (2005), p. 15]. Nevertheless, Drestke does not address the question why the non-transmissibility of reasons should be left without further explanation. In- stead of asking what lies beneath non-transmissibility in general, he focuses his discussion on perceptual scenarios, the reason being that perception is the chief route to our knowledge of the world around us, maybe the only route to that knowledge, and perceptual states do not transmit their warrants. I see wine in the cup, and there being wine in the cup logically implies there not being coloured water in the cup. However, nobody would say that what I see in the cup is not coloured water, i.e., that it is not coloured water that is in the cup. Non-transmissibility is out of the question. Fine; but why are reasons not in general transmissible? Drestke essayed the second explanation in some of his earlier papers [cf. Drestke (1970); (1981)]. You can explain why the animals in the enclo- sure are zebras because of its spaciousness, which allows them to move freely. Alternatively, because the plot of land is flat; or because the condi- tions are appropriate for a water line to be laid; or because in zoos zebras procreate best in plots like that. Many reasons would be worth assessing. Anyway, the reason you give explains why the animals in the enclosure are zebras and not lions, elephants or cleverly painted mules. (Why are they cleverly painted mules? — Because people expect to see zebras when they go
The Gettier Problem and the Demands of Inquiry 61
limits strictly marked by those alternatives acknowledged by the inquirers in the specific situation they are, as usually happens, then those principles are to conform to the demands of inquiry. If it is thought that they fix the transitions among propositions which are allowed independent of the entitlements in which those propositions figure, then the way has been paved for Gettier Problems and other puzzles to come up.^8 The wrong view here may be, as Dewey liked to put it, that logical forms “are logically prior and external to in- quiry” [Dewey (1950), p. 23]. By acknowledging this we free ourselves from the Gettier Problems’ grip on epistemology and explain away their intricacies.^9
Departamento de Filosofía Universidad de Granada Campus de Cartuja E-18011 Granada, Spain E-Mail: acero@ugr.es
NOTES
(^1) I follow and restrict myself to standard cases of the Gettier Problem, i.e. those
put forward in Gettier 1963. I will leave aside a different kind of Gettier Problem, namely, that in which perceptual beliefs and perceptual justified evidence are getti- ered. As for this second kind of case, see Goldman (1976). (^2) This is what most analyses of Gettier cases seem to assume. I do not argue for
this point here. (^3) My explanation of why there is a Gettier Problem concerning whether S
knows that something is P reinforces Lewis’ evaluation of this problem as against those provided by Stewart and Heller. It is context that can push us to ask for water- marks and dates on our titles to justify our knowledge claims. See Heller (1999), Lewis (1996), Cohen (1998). (^4) See Dewey [(1938): chapters I, VI, X and XV]. (^5) See Dewey [(1938), pp. 7f]. (^6) The same point could also be made in terms of Hintikka’s interrogative ap-
proach to the dynamics of scientific inquiry. One idea of his, set forth quite a few years ago, is that the conditions of answerhood are not absolute. What counts as an answer either to a “What Is Like”-question or to a “Who-” and a “Which”-question does not depend only on the question itself, but is relative to the state of the ques- tioner’s knowledge. See Hintikka (1981: 72 ff). Relying on this insight, it is straight- forward to argue that the inquirer’s knowledge behind the process of providing an answer to a “What Is Like”-question is different from that behind a “Who-” and a “Which”-question. “What Is Like”-inquiries and “Who”- and “Which”-inquiries de- mand from their agents quite diverse presuppositions. As for the notions of question, answer and presupposition, see Halonen, Mutanen and Hintikka (1999). A related ap- proach, based on the insight that the logical form of ‘S knows that p ’is ‘S knows that
62 Juan José Acero
p rather than q (for some proposition q )’, has been recently argued for. See Morton and Karjalainen (2003); Schaffer (2007). (^7) The last lines closely follow a text in Drestke [(1970), pp. 44f]. (^8) Many accept nowadays that the principle of modus ponens fails for condition-
als whose consequents are conditionals as well. See McGee (1985). Peacocke [(2004), chapter 3] argues that this inference principle is subject to entitlement’s conditions. Though I will not discuss this question, an explanation of why this principle of infer- ence can fail may be given along the lines sketched above. (^9) The research presented in this paper has been financed by the Spanish Minis-
try of Science and Education (Ministerio de Ciencia y Educación) through the HUM2007-62367/FISO project. It has also benefitted from the many comments, sug- gestions and criticisms generously provided by Ángel García Rodríguez (Murcia Uni- versity) and Manuel de Pinedo (Granada University).
REFERENCES
COHEN, S. (1998), “Contextualist Solutions to Epistemological Problems: Scepticism, Gettier, and the Lottery”, Australasian Journal of Philosophy , vol. 76, pp. 289-306. DEWEY, J. (1938), Logic. The Theory of Inquiry , New York: Henry Holt & Co. DRETSKE, F. (1970), “Epistemic Operators”, Journal of Philosophy , vol. 67, pp. 1007-