Docsity
Docsity

Prepare for your exams
Prepare for your exams

Study with the several resources on Docsity


Earn points to download
Earn points to download

Earn points by helping other students or get them with a premium plan


Guidelines and tips
Guidelines and tips

The Debate on Perceptual Experiences: Content and Arguments for Skepticism - Prof. Jeffrey, Study notes of Introduction to Philosophy

The concept of perceptual experiences and the debate surrounding their contents. The author discusses the arguments for and against the idea that perceptual experiences have contents, touching on topics such as illusion and hallucination, the veil of perception, animal perception, and the representation of particulars. The document also addresses concerns about the directness of perceptual experience and the explanatory role of perceptions.

Typology: Study notes

Pre 2010

Uploaded on 09/17/2009

koofers-user-e2t
koofers-user-e2t 🇺🇸

10 documents

1 / 8

Toggle sidebar

This page cannot be seen from the preview

Don't miss anything!

bg1
What does it mean to say that perceptual experiences have
contents, and do they?
phil 93507
Jeff Speaks
August 25, 2009
1 Two aspects of perception: content and phenomenal character . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1
2 Why think that perceptual experiences have contents? . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 2
3 Arguments for skepticism about perceptual content . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 3
3.1 Johnston on veridical illusion and veridical hallucination . . . . . . . . . . . . . 3
3.2 Content and the ‘veil of perception’ . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 3
3.3 Some experiences lack content, so all do, part I: animal perception . . . . . . . . 4
3.4 Some experiences lack content, so all do, part II: illusions . . . . . . . . . . . . . 4
3.5 Directness and the representation of particulars . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 5
3.6 The explanatory role of experience . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 6
3.7 The argument from dispensability . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 7
1 Two aspects of perception: content and phenomenal character
Informal exposition of the two central terms for our discussion of perception: phenomenal char-
acter and content.
The phenomenal character of a perceptual experience is: how that experience feels; how it seems,
from the point of view of the perceiver; what it is like to have the experience. Two experiences
have just the same phenomenal character iff having one experience is indistinguishable from
having the other; if they seem the same ‘from the inside.’
The content of a perceptual experience is: the way that experience presents the world as being;
the way that world is, according to that experience; the way that world appears (looks, smells,
sounds) to be to the perceiver. The content of a perceptual experience determines the veridicality
conditions of that experience: it determines the way the world would have to be the experience
to be accurate.
(Compare the way you would explain talk about the content of beliefs to an undergraduate. You
would say that the content of a belief is the way the world is, according to that belief; the way
the believer takes the world to be; and that the content of the belief determines the way the
world would have to be in order for the belief to be true.)
Pautz (2009) objects that explaining ‘content’ talk in this way trivializes debates about whether
experiences have contents and about what those contents are. He is right that, on this construal,
pf3
pf4
pf5
pf8

Partial preview of the text

Download The Debate on Perceptual Experiences: Content and Arguments for Skepticism - Prof. Jeffrey and more Study notes Introduction to Philosophy in PDF only on Docsity!

What does it mean to say that perceptual experiences have

contents, and do they?

phil 93507

Jeff Speaks

August 25, 2009

1 Two aspects of perception: content and phenomenal character.............. 1 2 Why think that perceptual experiences have contents?.................. 2 3 Arguments for skepticism about perceptual content.................... 3 3.1 Johnston on veridical illusion and veridical hallucination............. 3 3.2 Content and the ‘veil of perception’......................... 3 3.3 Some experiences lack content, so all do, part I: animal perception........ 4 3.4 Some experiences lack content, so all do, part II: illusions............. 4 3.5 Directness and the representation of particulars.................. 5 3.6 The explanatory role of experience......................... 6 3.7 The argument from dispensability.......................... 7

1 Two aspects of perception: content and phenomenal character

Informal exposition of the two central terms for our discussion of perception: phenomenal char- acter and content.

The phenomenal character of a perceptual experience is: how that experience feels; how it seems, from the point of view of the perceiver; what it is like to have the experience. Two experiences have just the same phenomenal character iff having one experience is indistinguishable from having the other; if they seem the same ‘from the inside.’

The content of a perceptual experience is: the way that experience presents the world as being; the way that world is, according to that experience; the way that world appears (looks, smells, sounds) to be to the perceiver. The content of a perceptual experience determines the veridicality conditions of that experience: it determines the way the world would have to be the experience to be accurate.

(Compare the way you would explain talk about the content of beliefs to an undergraduate. You would say that the content of a belief is the way the world is, according to that belief; the way the believer takes the world to be; and that the content of the belief determines the way the world would have to be in order for the belief to be true.)

Pautz (2009) objects that explaining ‘content’ talk in this way trivializes debates about whether experiences have contents and about what those contents are. He is right that, on this construal,

it is very plausible that experiences have contents. But that is because it is very plausible that experiences have contents. I think that it is an overstatement to say that on this sort of view the claim that perceptual experiences have contents is trivial. Some people do seem to deny this claim. (After all, some people deny the corresponding claim about belief and thought.) But Pautz is right that oftentimes when people say that they are denying that experiences have contents, they are denying something much stronger than the claim that in visual experiences, for example, there is a way that the world visually seems to the subject. I’ll return to this below.

I think that Pautz is incorrect when he says that this sort of explanation of the content of perception trivializes debates about the nature of the contents of experience. Compare the case of the content of belief. We can agree that debates about the nature of the content of belief are nontrivial. Why should perception be any different?

At this point, the key thing is to understand, at least in a preliminary way, what it means to talk about the phenomenal character of an experience, and what it means to talk about the content of an experience. You should also see that these things at least seem conceptually distinct: for all we have said, there might be an interesting relation between the two, or there might not be.

One of the reasons why the philosophy of perception is so interesting is because perception is the arena in which these two paradigmatic ‘marks of the mental’ — intentionality and phenomenal character — seem to be most closely related. One of the central questions in the philosophy of perception, and one of the questions which we’re going to talk about, concerns the relationship between these two.

2 Why think that perceptual experiences have contents?

In my view, the claim that perceptual experiences have contents needs little positive argument, at least when read in the above way. The intuitive view is surely that (e.g.) visual experiences present the world as being some way, that there is such a thing as the world visually appearing to be a certain way. At least, this seems as much the pre-theoretic view as the view that beliefs have contents. The interesting question, I think, is whether any of the arguments which have been given against perceptual content should lead us to give this view up.

But there are three standard kinds of arguments given for perceptual content, each of which is a kind of ‘best explanation’ argument:

  • Thinking of perceptions as having contents provides the most natural treatment of illu- sion and hallucination. It is plausible, pretheoretically, that illusions involve some mis- taken/false representation of the world. But one can have an illusory experience which one knows to be illusory. In that case, one does not have a belief with a false content — so what sort of state could have the false content? A very natural answer is: the perceptual state itself. Your perceptual experience is giving you a false picture of your environment. (This is not to say that there is no other way to think about illusion — just that this is one very natural understanding of the distinction between illusion and veridical experience.) For a nice discussion of this, and a critical discussion of views of illusion which avoid commitment to perceptual contents, see Byrne (2009), §V-VI; for an opposed view of illusion, see Brewer (2007a).
  • The view that perceptual experiences have contents is the best explanation of our ability to have contentful thoughts about our environment.
  • The view that experiences have contents is the best explanation of the fact that we can

are, which is what makes all contentful representation of that reality in thought even so much as possible.”

Why this worry seems more serious if you think of the contents of experience as Fregean senses.

A connection between this sort of worry and the problem about objects vs. contents of perception above.

3.3 Some experiences lack content, so all do, part I: animal perception

The view that perceptual experiences have content is naturally interpreted as the view that all perceptual experiences have content. It is difficult to see how having content could be an accidental feature of a type of mental state.

Alston (2005) argues that it is at least possible, and is probably actually the case, that some perceptual experiences lack content:

“It would suffice to establish that possibility to point out perceivers to whom objects look in certain ways and who are not at a stage of cognitive development that enables them to mentally represent SOA’s as obtaining.... if we take lower animals of the order of frogs and insects who do have perceptual capacities, it is very plausible both that objects consciously appear to them in certain ways and that they are incapable of doing anything that could properly be called representing those objects as having certain properties.”

Why think that frogs and insects are incapable of perceptually representing objects as having properties?

3.4 Some experiences lack content, so all do, part II: illusions

As Brewer (2006) points out, it seems to follow from the idea that perceptions have content that some perceptual experiences could misrepresent the world: they could have as their content a false proposition. It is also natural for the believer in perceptual content to think of illusions and hallucinations as cases of this kind. This appears to be a strength of the view that perceptions have contents; but Brewer thinks that it is a problem for the view. His basic idea is that the possibility of falsity conflicts with the kind of direct access that perception gives us to the world; the problem is

“The incompatibility, between this idea that perceptual experience consists in direct conscious access to constituents of the physical world themselves, and the possibility of falsity in perceptual content which is characteristic of any form of [the view that perceptions have content]”

So far this is hardly an argument. But Brewer doesn’t rely on this intuition; he argues that the view that perceptions have contents can’t give a convincing treatment of illusions like the Muller-Lyer illusion. According to the view that perceptions have content, in the case of such illusions the content of one’s experience is a false proposition. But Brewer (2006, 2007b) thinks that it is hard to see what this proposition could be, for the following reasons:

  1. Either one line must be represented as longer than it is, or the other must be represented as shorter than it is. But it is implausible to think that my experience of the lines represents them as being a determinate amount longer, or shorter, than they are. Reply: some views of perceptual experience think of the contents of perceptions as invariably determinate. But this is an inessential aspect of the view that perceptions have content and, in my view, not a very attractive one. Why not think that perceptions, like thoughts, can represent one line as longer than another without representing it as some determinate length longer than the other?
  2. Your experience represents the four endpoints of the two lines as being where they really are; your experience of the location of the endpoints is veridical. But you also represent the lines as of different lengths; so the content of your experience as a whole is a necessarily false proposition. Reply 1: indeterminacy again. Also some worries about what ‘where your experience represents the endpoints as being’ means. Reply 2: perhaps in this kind of case one’s perceptual experience has a contradictory proposition as its content.
  3. The ‘dynamic’ version of the illusion, on which the hashes coming off of the endpoints shrink till they vanish. The view that experiences have content is committed to the view that you represent the lines as gradually changing in length. But this is not the way it seems; perceptually, the lengths of the two lines appear to remain constant. Reply: This is the most interesting of Brewer’s cases. I am inclined to say that your experi- ence represents the lines as of different lengths, and then at some point comes to represent them as the same length, but that this change comes to pass without your representing either line as changing in length over time. I don’t see that this involves your perceptual experience at any time as having an impossible proposition as its content. Of course it is true that the content of your experience at the later time is inconsistent with its content at an earlier time, but that is what we’d expect, given that your perceptual experience initially represents the lines as having a different length and later as having the same length.

3.5 Directness and the representation of particulars

A second way of developing the worry that thinking of perceptions as having contents makes perceptual experience unacceptable indirect is due to Bill Brewer.

“Suppose that you see a particular red football — call it Ball. According to (CV), your perceptual experience is to be characterized by its representational content. Let us take it for granted that this content makes singular reference to Ball. Your experience therefore represents that Ball is a specific general way, F, which such objects may be. Whichever way this is supposed to be, its identification requires making a determinate specification of one among indefinitely many possible generalizations from Ball itself. Ball has colour, shape, size, weight, age, cost, and so on. So perception must begin by making a selection amongst all of these, according to (CV). Furthermore, and far more importantly for my present purposes, on any given such dimension — colour, or shape, say — the specification in experience of a determinate general way that your perception supposedly represents Ball as being requires further crucial abstraction. Supposing that your experience is veridical, it must be determinate to what extent, and in which ways, Balls actual colour or shape might vary consistently with the truth of the relevant perceptual content. This is really just to highlight the fact that (CV) is

thinking. But I don’t see why we should want to do that, or why we have to. McDowell, for one, sees this clearly in Mind and World:

“If we say that there must be a rational constraint on thought from outside it, so as to ensure a proper acknowledgement of the independence of reality, we put ourselves at the mercy of a familiar kind of ambiguity. “Thought” can mean the act of thinking; but it can also mean the content of a piece of thinking: what someone thinks. Now if we are to give due acknowledgement to the independence of reality, what we need is a constraint from outside thinking and judging... The constraint does not need to be from outside thinkable contents.” (28)

3.7 The argument from dispensability

Here is how Alston (2005) describes his opposition to the attribution of contents to perceptions:

“My central argument against [the view that perceptions have contents] is that we lack a sufficient reason for positing any such representation. The first point to note here is that in the absence of such a sufficient reason there is no basis for attribut- ing a representative function to PE. The only other basis there could be is that PE presents itself, is experienced as, a representation. But that is clearly not the case. When something I see looks a certain way to me (conical, red... ) it doesnt appear on the face of it be a representation of anything. The mind is not irresistibly conveyed to something it is representing the way the mind is when one looks at a (realistic) paint- ing or a photograph. The experience is not of that sort. Phenomenologically it has the character of a presentation of an object as being such-and-such. The experience terminates in the object presented without, so far as it appears, functioning to put S in mind of something else. Hence we need a reason beyond the phenomenological character of the experi- ence to take it to be a representation.” (275-6)

(For related sentiments about the dispensability of content attributions to perceptual experiences, see Crane (2009).)

What is the argument here? Could we make an analogous point about mental states which uncontroversially have contents, like judgements?

There is a worry here that the disagreement is merely verbal. When Alston says “Phenomeno- logically it has the character of a presentation of an object as being such-and-such” this seems to me to be pretty much the same thing as “it represents the object as being such-and-such.” Alston would not agree. But what does he require of states having contents that perceptions lack (or at least seem to lack)?

References

William Alston, 2005. Perception and Representation. Philosophy and Phenomenological Re- search 70:253–289.

Bill Brewer, 2006. Perception and Content. European Journal of Philosophy 14(2):165–181.

Bill Brewer, 2007a. How to Account for Illusion. ms..

Bill Brewer, 2007b. Perception and its Objects. Philosophical Studies 132:87–97.

Alex Byrne, 2009. Experience and Content. Philosophical Quarterly 59(236):429–451.

John Campbell, 2002a. Berkeley’s Puzzle. In Imagination, Conceivability, and Possibility, edited by Tamar Gendler and John O’Leary-Hawthorne, 127–144. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

John Campbell, 2002b. Reference and Consciousness. New York: Oxford University Press.

Tim Crane, 2009. Is Perception a Propositional Attitude? Philosophical Quarterly 59(236):453–

Mark Johnston, 2006. Better than Mere Knowledge? The Function of Sensory Awareness. In Perceptual Experience, edited by Tamar Szab’o Gendler and John Hawthorne, 260–290. New York: Oxford University Press.

John McDowell, 1994. Mind and World. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Adam Pautz, 2009. What Are the Contents of Experiences? Philosophical Quarterly 59(236):483–