








Study with the several resources on Docsity
Earn points by helping other students or get them with a premium plan
Prepare for your exams
Study with the several resources on Docsity
Earn points to download
Earn points by helping other students or get them with a premium plan
Community
Ask the community for help and clear up your study doubts
Discover the best universities in your country according to Docsity users
Free resources
Download our free guides on studying techniques, anxiety management strategies, and thesis advice from Docsity tutors
The challenges of democracy in a globalized world where decision-making is not solely in the hands of states or central authorities. The author explores the concept of deliberative polyarchy, a multi-centered architecture for decision-making that combines local problem-solving with disciplined comparisons across units. The document emphasizes the importance of transparency, participation, and the role of non-state organizations in this process.
Typology: Exercises
1 / 14
This page cannot be seen from the preview
Don't miss anything!
Global Democracy, Without the State
1. Democracy and the State Much of our thinking about democracy assumes the existence of a state: by “state” I mean a politically organized society, with a central authority, operating over a territory, that monopolizes the legitimate use of force and has a wide range of policy competences (employment, environment, health, product safety, domestic security, research/development, etc.). Our standard conceptions of democracy—current paradigms of democraticness—are linked to this institutional setting. The idea is, roughly, that policy-makers are held accountable to citizens through regular competitive elections, against a background of basic liberties of speech and association. Citizens debate issues, with the debate organized in part by competing parties with distinct views; they choose representatives, and those representatives make policies and hold officials—executives and regulators—accountable for the articulation and implementation of those policies. Thus we have a highly mediated form of accountability to citizens as a body of equals. This was not always the understanding of democracy. In Democracy and Its Critics , Robert Dahl writes about two major transformations of democracy: first, the development of direct democracy in Greek city-states, then second, the development of representative democracy in the United States and early modern Europe, as a response to, among other things, a growth in the size of political units. These are both forms of democracy in that they are both ways in which the interests, beliefs, principles, and ideals of equal persons who are subject to
collective decisions are brought to bear on making those decisions: ways that the authorization to exercise power results from the collective decisions of the equal persons who are governed by that power. The modern conception—with representation and party competition—emerges in response to demands of responsiveness and accountability in the setting of a modern state, with the indicia of Westphalian sovereignty. It took considerable invention, both intellectually and practically, to see how the abstract idea of democracy could be brought to bear on a modern, centralized, large, sovereign state. There are of course serious questions about the democratic credentials of laws and policies chosen by elected officials, or by agents (administrative agencies) acting under their supervision: not least because laws and policies are so loosely linked to informal public discussion and processes of opinion formation, so the idea that they issue from processes of collective decision- making that treat people as equals is a matter of disagreement: the agency relations extending from people to policy-makers are pretty weak. But I don’t wish to pursue those questions here. I want instead to focus on the thought—suggested by current discussion of the prospects for a more global democracy—that we may be witnessing the emergence of a new challenge to democracy that will require a comparable reconceptualization of what democracy arrangements consist in. The question is: how should we think about democracy and democratizing decision-making when the decision maker is not a state, or any other form of central authority, with the characteristics of a Westphalian sovereign—both because of some disaggregation within states, so that agencies themselves operate in policy coordination as parts of global networks (see
They do not fit because the parts act neither as independently as separate states nor as parts of a single state. The regulatory processes involve, in particular, a decentralized specification of policy standards (say, in employment policy), disciplined by a systematic comparison with standards in other locations, with the aim of mutual correction and improvement rather than convergence on a single standard or policy. So while there are reasonable demands for the democratization of the EU, it is not clear how to use our ideas of democracy to assess the complicated mix.
intergovernmentalism at the level of global institutions. This line of thought is suggested in Kymlicka and Dahl, and by Stiglitz in his discussion of reforms of voting rights and improved transparency for the major international economics institutions (Bank, IMF, and WTO). Stiglitz emphasizes the role of governance reforms in ensuring policy that is more attentive to the needs of beneficiaries—who are currently unrepresented in discussion—he also thinks of the institutions as public, and of the governance reforms—both accountability and transparency—as suited to their public status. But world state and perfected intergovernmentalism do not exhaust the possibilities for thinking about current political developments and prospects for democracy. As Ruggie emphasizes in his account of the issues of global governance and the emerging global public domain, there is now something that we can call a global public sphere with a politics focused on issues labor standards, environmental policy, health policy, trade, human rights, economic development—and with emerging institutions, norms, movements, and (contested) forms of discourse, in which the agents are not at all confined to states or officials. Even more than in the case of the EU, we see an emerging politics, that is functionally differentiated (different institutions and organizations for different problems) and that lacks a regulatory center. And, once more, while there is discussion about democratizing global governance, it is not clear what that democratization might look like. In both cases, we see is the emergence of new arrangements of collective problem-solving. In each case, the problems they address are urgent, and in each case the new arrangements emerge because existing institutions seem inadequate to handling them. Moreover, the tasks of these new arrangements
education, adequate compensation for workers, etc.) emerge in different locations, which are not only geographically distinct but culturally, economically, and politically distinct. While the differences in location suggest a need for differences in solution, the commonality of problems indicates a need to test and discipline local solutions against those adopted elsewhere: the aim is not to achieve uniformity, but to pool information, identify best practices, and compare solutions across locations. Consider the cases of labor standards, where it seems clear that different standards for wages and working conditions are suited to different levels of development, and that uniformity represents a mix of regulatory imperialism and protectionism. So what seems desirable are arrangements that are friendly to local experimentation in the policy area in question, that pool the results of those experiments in ways that permits outsiders to monitor and learn from those efforts, that identify best (or anyway, better) practices, and that require comparisons of solutions across sites. And this suggests a very abstract architecture of what I will call “deliberative polyarchy”—“deliberative” because decision-making involves reasoning about solutions to problems, “polyarchy” because the architecture is essentially multi-centered. Consider first the individual decision-making units. Diversity implies that decision-making in each needs to draw on local knowledge and values. As each unit is distinct, none does best by simply copying solutions adopted by others, though they may do well to treat those solutions as baselines from which to move. Local problem solving is well-suited to bringing the relevant local knowledge and values to bear in making decisions. Deliberative participation
helps because it encourages the expression of differences in outlook, and the provision of information more generally. But the same concern for a form of decision-making that it is attentive to unexplored possibilities and unintended consequences requires institutionalization of links among local units—in particular, the institutionalization of links that require separate deliberative units to consider their own proposals against benchmarks provided by other units. A natural place to look for promising alternatives—including alternatives previously unimagined in the local setting—is in the experience of units facing analogous problems. So we need deliberative coordination: deliberation among units of decision-making directed both to learning jointly from their several experiences, and improving the institutional possibilities for such learning—a system with continuous discussion across separate units about current best practice and better ways of ascertaining it. This abstractly-described architecture is pervasive in the EU (see the Cohen-Sabel paper). Local, or, more exactly, lower level actors—govenments or national peak organizations of various kinds within the EU; regions, provinces or sub-national associations within these, and so on down to whatever neighborhood is relevant to the problem at hand—are given autonomy to experiment with their own solutions to broadly defined problems of public policy. In return they furnish central or higher-level units with rich information regarding their goals as well as the progress they are making towards achieving them. They agree as well to respect the framework rights of democratic procedure and substance as these are elaborated in the course of experimentation itself. The periodic pooling of results reveals the defects of parochial solutions, and allows the elaboration of standards for comparing local achievements, exposing poor
First, then, we can promote the democraticness of deliberative polyarchy by insisting on the requirement of disciplined comparisons across different efforts at problem-solving. Those comparisons bring the different experiences in those diverse places to bear on problem-solving in each location. Deliberative polyarchy is, in short, a way to systematically pool a wide range of ideas and experiences: it thus creates, in effect, a kind of dispersed public political-policy discussion across different locations, and it disciplines solutions in each location by reference to that broader discussion—so influence extends across locations not through a uniform solution established by a regulatory center, but by establishing standards that others need to consider. Second, assume that arrangements of deliberative polyarchy form in distinct areas of concern. In the case of labor standards, for example, imagine a coordinated system of monitoring that would certify monitors to conduct audits of firms (also subject to independent audit), and also require that monitors report back their findings to the “super-monitor” constituted by international organizations such as the World Bank and International Labor Organization, together with international NGOs and international trade union confederations. This umpire organization would monitor the monitors, conduct inspections to verify their integrity, assure the comparability of monitoring data and methods, and make results publicly accessible. Firms that depend on consumer loyalty would be eager earn high grades. They would pressure less visible suppliers, and suppliers of suppliers, to follow suit. Activists, consumer groups, analysts, and journalists would use information to define acceptable behavior, press for improvements, and push the monitors to improve their methods and their standards. And the same will be true in other areas as well. Assuming a norm of
transparency, as well as protections of rights to associate and speak—all very substantial assumptions, of course—deliberative polyarchies, once constructed, will become the focus of debate and pressure from organizations that already exist to influence policy in these areas, as well as new organizations that see new opportunities for influence. That is, as arrangements of deliberative polyarchy crystallize, they will become the focus of political activity. There is of course a very large question—analogous to questions about conventional democracies, with substantial inequalities of resources—about the extent to which opportunities for influence will be equal, even if we assume transparency, and protections of expressive and associative liberties. Thinking of ways of foster such equality when deliberative polyarchy does not operate in the shadow of a state is a large task for democratic theory. But ensuring transparency, as well as the expressive and associative liberties, would certainly be a large first step. Third, a standard element of local problem-solving in emerging systems of deliberative polyarchy is participation by non-state organizations that bring some competence to the discussion of specific problems. Ruggie mentions five roles of such organizations: they implement policy (providing basic goods such as health and education, under contract with governments or international organizations), though it should be said that the distinction between a role in implementing policy and a role in designing it is hard to sustain; they play a role in generating, deepening, and implementing transnational norms; they help both to advance and to block international agreements; they coordinate with international actors to promote domestic change (boomerang effect); and they encourage transparency. But participation by groups with special competences naturally prompts concerns
distinct from other sorts of policy issues. But it is difficult to see a fundamental distinction here between foreign policy and large areas of domestic policy. In any case, Dahl’s own concern appears to shift from policy substance to the decline in citizen influence that comes with an increase in the size of political units: the influence of Swedes over their own parliament is greater than their influence over the European parliament. But suggests a case for having no large political units at all, which is also not Dahl’s point. And the fact that this is not the concern emerges in the following comment: “To achieve a level of popular control that is anywhere near the level already existing within democratic countries, international organizations would have to solve several problems about as well as they are now dealt with in democratic countries” (30-31). He mentions five conditions which amount, in effect, to the view that they would need to look like conventional democracies: with, among other things, party competition and legislative control of agencies. The skepticism, then, seems not to be at all directed against the possibility of a eurodemocracy or a global democracy, but against democratizing intergovernmental organizations, and that seems to be well-taken. But then he adds a concern that we met with in the discussion of Miller and is suggested by Kymlicka as well: namely, that the successful operation of a democracy requires a willingness to accept burdens (at least the near-term burdens of legislative losers), and that such willingness may require some kind of shared culture and common identity: this is the idea, on one formulation, that states needs nations. Perhaps so, and successful functioning certainly requires trust. But the idea of deliberative polyarchy is that the experience of jointly
addressing issues of common concern may itself suffice to create sufficient trust, that a thinner, less demanding sense of commonality