Docsity
Docsity

Prepare for your exams
Prepare for your exams

Study with the several resources on Docsity


Earn points to download
Earn points to download

Earn points by helping other students or get them with a premium plan


Guidelines and tips
Guidelines and tips

Ethical Pluralism by Peter Schaber, Lecture notes of Ethics

Ethical Pluralism in explain ross ethical pluralism, hooker's objection, justification of ethical pluralism, unity of morality, moral conflict and self - evident principles.

Typology: Lecture notes

2021/2022

Uploaded on 03/31/2022

barnard
barnard 🇺🇸

3.9

(9)

230 documents

1 / 19

Toggle sidebar

This page cannot be seen from the preview

Don't miss anything!

bg1
1
Ethical Pluralism
Peter Schaber (University of Zurich)
1. Ross’ Ethical Pluralism
2. Hooker’s Objection
3. The Justification of Ethical Pluralism
4. An Unconnected Heap of Duties?
5. The Unity of Morality
6. Self-Evident Principles?
7. Moral Conflicts
8. Conclusion
Ethical pluralism is not the view that there is a plurality of comprehensive moral
views in a modern society, something John Rawls calls the fact of pluralism.
Ethical pluralism is a normative theory which deals with the structure of moral
theories, that is, theories about what is morally right and wrong. And the
central claim of ethical pluralism is the following:
(EP) There is a plurality of moral norms that cannot be redu-
ced to one basic norm.
This doctrine is opposed to all monistic views of morality such as for
instance utilitarianism with its principle of utility as the basic norm of morality
or such as the Kantian ethics with the categorical imperative as the basic norm
of morality. The idea of ethical pluralism goes back to the work of William
David Ross. In his book “The Right and the Good” he distinguishes kinds of
moral duties1: (1) Duties of fidelity and reparation; (2) Duties of gratitude; (3)
1 Ross (1930) , 2 1.
pf3
pf4
pf5
pf8
pf9
pfa
pfd
pfe
pff
pf12
pf13

Partial preview of the text

Download Ethical Pluralism by Peter Schaber and more Lecture notes Ethics in PDF only on Docsity!

Ethical Pluralism

Peter Schaber (University of Zurich)

  1. Ross’ Ethical Pluralism
  2. Hooker’s Objection
  3. The Justification of Ethical Pluralism
  4. An Unconnected Heap of Duties?
  5. The Unity of Morality
  6. Self-Evident Principles?
  7. Moral Conflicts
  8. Conclusion Ethical pluralism is not the view that there is a plurality of comprehensive moral views in a modern society, something John Rawls calls the fact of pluralism. Ethical pluralism is a normative theory which deals with the structure of moral theories, that is, theories about what is morally right and wrong. And the central claim of ethical pluralism is the following: (EP) There is a plurality of moral norms that cannot be redu- ced to one basic norm. This doctrine is opposed to all monistic views of morality such as for instance utilitarianism with its principle of utility as the basic norm of morality or such as the Kantian ethics with the categorical imperative as the basic norm of morality. The idea of ethical pluralism goes back to the work of William David Ross. In his book “The Right and the Good” he distinguishes kinds of moral duties^1 : (1) Duties of fidelity and reparation; (2) Duties of gratitude; (3) (^1) Ross (1930), 21.

Duties of justice; (4) Duties of beneficence; (5) duties of self-improvement and (6) Duties of non-maleficience. These duties are all basic duties which cannot be derived from other duties. That one should keep one’s promises, that good should be distributed justly, that one should not harm other on purpose are all duties which, accor- ding to Ross, do not have to be justified, because they are self-evident for all those who have “reached sufficient mental maturity and have given sufficient attention to the proposition”^2. In Ross’ view they are in the same way self- evident as mathematical axioms are. This is in a condensed form the idea of ethical pluralism Ross argues for. Moral norms do not have an archimedian point. There are rather different considerations which are relevant for morality: Morality is not just about maximizing well-being, not just about respecting the autonomy of others, not just about mutual benefit and other things more. Morality is, so to speak, about irreducibly different things. This lecture is a lecture about ethical pluralism. More precisely, it is about the reasons for being an ethical pluralist. I will argue that a moral theory cannot be developed independently of what we really think about moral matters. And because of the fact that our moral thinking is irreducbly plura- listic, ethical pluralism should be accepted.

  1. Ross’ Ethical Pluralism Let us first have a closer look at what Ross had in mind. Ross calls his basic duties prima facie duties. He introduces this term in the following way: A prima facie duty is a duty we have to fulfill, as long as it does not collide with another prima facie duty. A promise I gave has to be kept, provided there is no other (^2) Ross (1930), 29.

Why does Ross think that ethical pluralism is true? According to Ross, monistic moral theories are wrong because they favour a certain type of social relation: the Kantian theory, for instance, thinks that the only morally signifi- cant relation others stand to me is that of being a fellow human; the utilitarian sees the others only as “possible beneficaries by my actions”. But to this Ross adds: “They do stand in this relation to me, and this relation is morally significant. But they may also stand to me in the relation of promisee to promiser, of creditor to debtor, of wife to husband, of child to parent, of friend to friend, of fellow countryman to fellow countryman, and the like; and each of these relations is the foundation of a prima facie duty, which is more or less incumbent on me accor ding to the circumstances of the case.”^5 According to Ross, monistic moral theories cannot account for the diversity of the morally relevant types of social relations. The idea that the different types of social relations are morally relevant, that prima facie duties are based on them, is for Ross not in need of a further justification. It seems to be self- evident. But this idea can be questioned. Why is the type of social relation utilitarians favour, for instance, not the only morally relevant relation? An answer to this question can be given by another argument Ross puts forward in favour of ethical pluralism: According to this argument, ethical pluralism is true, because it fits well with the way we really think about moral questions. We do not think that we should always maximize the good; that we should keep our promises only if they by doing that we promote the overall well-being. On the contrary. We think that there are situations where we should keep our promises, even if breaking them would make many persons better off.^6 The duty to promote overall well-being can be outweighed by our duty to (^5) Ross (1930), 19. (^6) See Ross (1930), 18.

keep our promises. Thus, according to what we really think about moral questions, morality is not just about maximizing well-being. And this fits well with ethical pluralism. As Ross puts it: “I have tried to show that a system which admits only of one intuition is false to what we all really think about what makes acts right or wrong.”^7 And this for Ross a good reasons for being an ethical pluralist.

  1. Hooker’s Objection But is the fact that the moral theory fits well with what we think really a good reason to be an ethical pluralist. But before I will discuss this problem, let me just deal with an objection that has been put forward quite recently by Brad Hooker.^8 Hooker argues that ethical pluralism is not the only moral theory that fits well with what we really think about moral matters. He thinks that this also applies to a certain version of rule-consequentialism. The basic principle of rule-consequentialism says: ‘Act according to rules which maximize the good, given all would comply with these rules’. Hooker thinks that this is not a rule we should follow in our everyday life. We should rather follow secondary rules which are based on the mentioned principle. “The theory selects rules by whether their inculcation could reasonably be ex- pected to maximise the good. The theory evaluates acts by reference to the rules thus selected. There is in the theory no overarching commitment to maximise the good.”^9 (53)) Hooker also thinks that the good is not only promoted when we promote overall well-being but also when we promote fairness. We have to maximise (^7) Ros (1939), 83. (^8) Hooker (1996). (^9) Hooker (1996), 53.

I do not think so. A monistic moral theory such as Hooker’s rule- consequentialism might justify the same moral duties than Ross’ ethical pluralism does. This would not imply that a monistic theory would fit well with what we really think about moral questions. What Ross has in mind by saying that ethical pluralism fits well with what we really think is not the catalogue of moral duties he proposes. He rather means the properties we refer to in justifying why we think that actions are right or wrong. We call actions right, because they are just or because they promote the well-being of others and we call actions wrong, because they are cruel or because they are harmful. And Ross’ point is: There is no property such as the property of utility-maximizing that dominates our moral thinking. There are irreducibly different properties that make actions right and wrong. Ethical pluralism fits well with what we really think about what makes acts right and wrong. Here ethical pluralism differs from any form of ethical monism. It is in this respect that ethical pluralism fares better than its monistic rivals.

  1. The Justification of Ethical Pluralism One can argue that the harmony between ethical pluralism and what we really think about what makes actions right and wrong is no reason to be an ethical pluralist. It would only be a reason if we could rightly assume that what we really think about makes actions right and wrong is true, that is, that we are not wrong in our everyday moral thinking. And - one could argue - this cannot be assumed. It is the task of a moral theory to develop procedures that allow us to test our everyday moral beliefs, which could lead to the conclusion that many, if not most of our moral beliefs have to be revised or abandoned. Ross himself was fully aware of this problem: “In what has preceded, a good deal of use has been made of ‘what we really think’ about moral questions; a certain theory has been rejected because it does

not agree with what we really think. It might be said that this is in principle wrong: that we should not be content to expound what our present moral consci- ousness tells us but should aim at criticism of our existing moral consciousness in the light of theory.”^10 Ross thinks that a moral theory cannot be developed independently of what we really think, because we cannot give up our basic moral beliefs. Imagine that we were told that promise-keeping was wrong or torturing another person for fun was right. According to Ross, we could not seriously hold such views. We could try, but we could not succeed in doing it. Ross says that he himself could never believe that promise-keeping is right only if it promotes overall well-being, “in spite of a very genuine attempt to do so. And I venture to think that most people will find the same”^11. In the same way it would be impossible to believe that harming others for fun would be right. And as a consequence a moral theory that would come up which such recommendations could not accepted as the right moral theory. This should not be taken as a remark about how difficult it is for us to change our moral thinking. Such a difficulty would hardly be of philosophical interest. It is something else that Ross has in mind here. His point is the following. We cannot not seriously think that we are fundamentally wrong in moral matters. There cannot be any doubt that it is right to keep the promises one made and wrong to harm others just for fun. And a theory that told us to see things in a different way could not be considered as a proper moral theory. One would think it is a theory about something else. Thus there is no room for a fundamental scepticism with regard to our moral views. (^10) Ross (1930), 39. (^11) Ross (1930), 40.

can even abandon them. But we do so not in the face of sense-perceptions, but rather in the face of well-considered moral views. Moral theories are right, provided they are compatible with well-considered moral views; views which have been formed under reliable conditions. Now we cannot assume that all these well-considered moral views are wrong, because otherwise moral theories could not be tested at all. Of course, one could think that moral theories cannot be tested (this is the noncognitivist view in ethcis). There are no sensible tests here, because there is no fact of the matter to be discovered in ethics. But this is not the way we talk about moral matters. A person who holds the view, for instance, that abortion is wrong, does not think that he just does not like abortion, he rather thinks that abortion is indeed wrong. The point is: Our understanding of moral judgements might be wrong; but if there is truth in ethics, then our moral views cannot be completely wrong. Because they themselves play the role play the role sense-perceptions play in the natural science: They provide us with the evidence needed to test and to form our moral theories. Thus, competent persons cannot be completely wrong: The right moral theory has to be compatible with their views. And this the reason why the right moral theory has to fit well what we really think about moral questions. So far Ross’ justification of ethical pluralism.

  1. An Unconnected Heap of Duties? Let me now turn to different objections that have been put forward against ethical pluralism. According to one objection we should not believe in ethical pluralism, because it provides us with an unconnected heap of moral duties and right- and wrong making properties. It does not provide us with what a satisfactory moral theory should provide us, namely with a coherent system. Monistic theories such as utilitarianism and the ethics of Kant succeed in doing

so: They can tell why a certain norm has to be seen as moral norm. As David Raphael puts it: “(Pluralism) gives a reasonably accurate picture of everyday judgement ... it does not meet the needs of a philosophical theory, which should try to show connec tions and should tie things up in a coherent system.”^15 Is this a good reason to reject Ross-style pluralism? I do not think so. First of all, it is not true that Ross is just coming up with a list of moral duties, that is to say, with a list of right- and wrong-making properties. Ross distinguishes between underived and derived duties. The duty, for instance, to comply with the law is derived from underived duties, namely the duty of gratitude, the duty of fidelity and the duty of beneficience. And the duty not to lie is derived from the underived duty of non-maleficience and the duty of fidelity. Thus Ross’ catalogue of duties is in any case not just an unconnected heap of duties. Moreover, Ross’ list of underived duties is not meant to be a final, rather a provisional list. This is important, because Ross’ proposal does not exclude the possibility that the given underived duties might be reduced to less than six or maybe even to one duty or one right- and wrong-making property. “If the objection is made, that this catalogue of the main types of duty is an un- systematic one resting on no logical principle, it may be replied, first, that it ma- kes no claim to being ultimate ... If further reflection discovers a perfect basis for this or for a better classification, so much for the better” (23). Ross does not hold the view that there is a single principle to be discovered to would allow us to tie things up in a coherent system. According to him, there is no reason to think so. But Ross has no proof that such a principle cannot exist. But before arguing that ethical pluralism cannot a satisfactory moral theory, because it doesn’t tie things up in a coherent system, we should consider the possibilty that there is no such basic principle of morality. “It might be wiser to (^15) Raphael (1981), 55.

them their importance.”^19 It is the justifiability of a norm, Scanlon thinks, that makes it a moral norm. If I have a moral duty to do x, than my not doing x could not be justified to others. The ethical pluralist cannot provide us with such a property that ties moral things up in a unified system. For the ethical pluralist an action is wrong, because the action is cruel, for instance, or unjust. But if Scanlon is right then more is to be said about moral wrongness and rightness. I think that this question cannot be answered in a general way. The question is rather: Can the idea of justifiability play the role it is supposed to play according to Scanlon? I think that the pluralist view fits better with what we really think about moral justification. We justify moral judgements such as ‘It is wrong to torture people’ by referring to properties such as ‘cruel’ or ‘harmful’ (‘it is wrong, because it’s cruel’). We think that actions are wrong because of they have such properties. Of course, we also think that these actions cannot be justified to others. But this is just due to the fact that they have these properties and that they are therefore wrong. And we should not carry them out because they have these properties. The fact that the action cannot be justified has no independent normative weight. It does not provide us with reasons for not carrying out the actions in question. The answer to the question ‘Do I have a reason not to torture John?’ would be ‘Yes, because it would be cruel to do so, or possibly because it would be wrong to act this way’. But certainly not: ‘Yes, because it could not be justified to others’. This is also the case, but it is just a consequence of the wrongness of this kind of action. (^19) Scanlon (1998), 176.

  1. Self-Evident Principles? Let me turn to another objection against ethical pluralism which has to do with Ross’ idea that the underived prima facie duties are self-evident. One can argue that there are no self-evident moral duties. There is widespread disagreement about which moral duties have to be considered as basic duties. And this shows that the justification of moral norms cannot rely on self-evidence, as Ross wants us to believe. First of all, I think that this objection takes the term ‘self-evidence’ in a way it has not been taken by Ross. According to him, the fact that a norm x is self-evident does not imply that everyone holds this norm to be valid. There can be disagreement about self-evident norms, because they are not self-evident for everyone. As Ross puts it: “The general principles of duty are obviously not self-evident from the beginning of our lives. How do they come to be so? The answer is, that they come to be self-evident to us just as mathematical axioms do. We find by experience that this couple of matches and that couple make four matches, that this couple of balls on a wire and that couple make four balls: and by reflection on these and similar discoveries we come to see that it is of the nature of two and two to make four. In a precisely similar way, we see the prima facie rightness of an act which would be the fulfilment of a particuar promise, and of another which would be the fulfilment of another promise, and when we reached sufficient maturity to think in general terms, we apprehend prima facie rightness to belong to the nature of any fulfilment of promise.”^20 Thus, the idea of self-evident moral principles is compatible with widespread disagreements about basic moral norms. Only those who really know what it means to break a promise, will grasp that the corresponding principle which tells us to keep our promises is self-evident.Only those who know what the (^20) Ross (1930), 32pp.

“(T)here is no principle by which we can draw the conclusion that it is on the whole right or on the whole wrong. In this respect the judgement as to the right- ness of a particular act is just like the judgement as to the beauty of a particular natural object or work of art ... our judgement is ... reached by ... the apprehensi on of ist particular beauties or particular defects.”^23 (31). But then, we can never be sure that we are right. We just have “more or less probable opinions”^24 with regard to the right solution of conflicts between prima facie duties (or conflicting right- and wrong making aspects of the situation). One could think that there is something wrong with such a conception of conflict-resolution. Rawls holds such a view. “If we cannot explain how these weights are to be determined by reasonable ethical criteria, the means of rational discussion have come to an end ... We should do what we can to formulate explicit principles for the priority problem ...”^25 Rawls suggests that this is what a moral theory has to aim at, because we want justified solutions of our moral problems. Ross discusses this problem: He thinks that other moral theories do not fare any better with regard to their capacity to solve moral conflicts. Moore’s ideal utilitarianism, for instance, has no rule to solve a conflict between “the production of two heterogenous goods, say pleasure and know- ledge, the ideal utilitarian theory can only fall back on an opinion, for which no logical basis can be offered, that one of the goods is greater; and this is no better than a similar opinion that one of the effects of our actions is more urgent”^26. The lack of rules for the solution of moral conflicts is not a special problem of ethical pluralism. (^23) Ross (1930), 31. (^24) Ross (1930), 31. (^25) Rawls (1971), 37. (^26) Ross (1930), 23.

But, more importantly, it is not clear whether an ethical pluralist is faced with a real difficulty here. If there is a irreducible plurality of basic prima facie duties and if there is no general rule for solving moral conflicts, then we might indeed have to rely on our judgement. And if our judgement does not provide us with solutions that are definitely right, rather with as Ross puts it with “more or less probable opinions”^27 , then it is exactly what a moral theory can provide us with. Again Ross: “(The) sense of our particular duty in particular circumstances, preceded and in- formed by the fullest reflection we can bestow on the act in all its bearings, is highly fallible, but it is the only guide we have to our duty.”^28 It might well be the case that monistic moral theories do also have limits with respect to their capacity to provide us with clear-cut answers to moral questi- ons. But even if this were not the case, and monistic theories were able to provide us with clear-cut answers to all moral questions, this would not necessarily be a reason that would speak in favour of them. To provide us with clear-cut answers is not part of the adequacy-conditions a moral theory has to fulfil. It is true, we are looking for the solutions of our moral problems; but we do not want to have just any solutions, we want the right solutions. And there is no reason to assume that a clear-cut solution is per se the right one. Some problems might just have no solution. If so, it is the task of an adequate moral theory just to tell that there is no solution.

  1. Conclusion Let me summarize. If ethical pluralism is true, there is no single principle that ties moral matters up in a coherent system. This does not mean that the list of (^27) Ross (1930), 31. (^28) Ross (1930), 42.

References Hooker B. (1996): Ross-style Pluralism versus Rule-Consequentialism, in Mind 105, 531-552. Raphael D.D. (1981): Moral Philosophy, Oxford. Rawls J. (1971): A Theory of Justice, Cambridge, Mass. Ross W.D. (19309: The Right and the God, Oxford.

  • (1939): Foundations of Ethics, Oxford. Scanlon Th. (1998): What We Owe To Each Other, Cambridge, Mass. Shafer-Landau R. (2003): Moral Realism. A Defence, Oxford.