Docsity
Docsity

Prepare for your exams
Prepare for your exams

Study with the several resources on Docsity


Earn points to download
Earn points to download

Earn points by helping other students or get them with a premium plan


Guidelines and tips
Guidelines and tips

Comments on National Self-Determination-Political Philosophy-Lecture Handout, Exercises of Political Philosophy

This lecture handout is for Political Philosophy course. It was assigned by Prof. Jalendu Pillai at Bharathidasan University. It includes: Comments, National, Selfdetermination, Boundaries, Theory, Nationalism, Understood, Characterization, Legitimacy

Typology: Exercises

2011/2012

Uploaded on 08/08/2012

sanjna
sanjna 🇮🇳

4.2

(6)

47 documents

1 / 12

Toggle sidebar

This page cannot be seen from the preview

Don't miss anything!

bg1
Global Justice, Spring 2003, 1
Comments on National Self-Determination
1. The Principle of Nationality
In Nations and Nationalism, Ernest Gellner says that “nationalism is a theory of
political legitimacy which requires that ethnic boundaries should not cut across
political ones.” Gellner’s characterization of nationalism should be understood as
deriving from two premises: first, a definition of nation in terms of ethnicity; and
second, the principle that national and political boundaries ought to coincide. Call
the latter the principle of nationality. The two premises are of course
independent.
Lets focus for now on the principle of nationality. In his account of
nationality, David Miller states the principle as follows: “it is valuable for the
boundaries of political units (paradigmatically, states) to coincide with national
boundaries” (82). And he distinguishes two elements of the principle, and,
correspondingly, two distinct strands of argument in its favor:
1. It is “valuable” for nations to have states (political units)
2. It is valuable for states to compromise a single nation (valuable to
comprise one, and valuable to comprise no more than one).
Now Miller’s official statement of the principle of nationality (which I have quoted)
is very weak, inasmuch as it says nothing about the importance of the value of
having political and national units coincide. But elsewhere Miller suggests
stronger formulations: for example that national communities living in a territory
have a “good claim [emphasis added] to political self-determination; there ought
docsity.com
pf3
pf4
pf5
pf8
pf9
pfa

Partial preview of the text

Download Comments on National Self-Determination-Political Philosophy-Lecture Handout and more Exercises Political Philosophy in PDF only on Docsity!

Comments on National Self-Determination

1. The Principle of Nationality In Nations and Nationalism , Ernest Gellner says that “nationalism is a theory of political legitimacy which requires that ethnic boundaries should not cut across political ones.” Gellner’s characterization of nationalism should be understood as deriving from two premises: first, a definition of nation in terms of ethnicity; and second, the principle that national and political boundaries ought to coincide. Call the latter the principle of nationality. The two premises are of course independent. Lets focus for now on the principle of nationality. In his account of nationality, David Miller states the principle as follows: “it is valuable for the boundaries of political units (paradigmatically, states) to coincide with national boundaries” (82). And he distinguishes two elements of the principle, and, correspondingly, two distinct strands of argument in its favor: 1. It is “valuable” for nations to have states (political units) 2. It is valuable for states to compromise a single nation (valuable to comprise one, and valuable to comprise no more than one). Now Miller’s official statement of the principle of nationality (which I have quoted) is very weak, inasmuch as it says nothing about the importance of the value of having political and national units coincide. But elsewhere Miller suggests stronger formulations: for example that national communities living in a territory have a “ good claim [emphasis added] to political self-determination; there ought

to be put in place an institutional structure that enables them to decide collectively matters that concern primarily their own community” (11). So there is a right to national self-determination: not an absolute right, but a “good claim.” Presumably, too, states have the authority to do what is required to build a nation. That is, presumably we should interpret the principle of nationality as claiming that the value of there being a single nation within a state is sufficiently great that states have the authority to foster a common national identity through law and public policy (in education, or regional development, or language policy, or policies on coinage). Of course some means—like expulsion or slaughter of national minorities to create homogeneity, or regulations on speech critical of the nation’s greatness—may be illegitimate, but the principle of nationality , as I am supposing Miller to interpret it, is more than an observation about what would be an attractive state of affairs. It is part of a normative account of the legitimate authority of the state. Comments on the Principle. I want to explore the argument that states are helped by having nations later on. But before getting to it I want to make two background points. First, the principle of nationality is a principle about political jurisdictions: whether the political unit in question is a sovereign state or a subnational unit in a federal system, the point of the principle is to make the case for a correspondence between jurisdictional and national boundaries. It is thus a stronger thesis—in any case a different one—than we find in Yael Tamir’s defense of national self-determination in her account of liberal nationalism. Tamir

that they are entitled to a territory; are capable of acting as a group; have a common history; and a shared public culture. Now the requirement of shared public culture may seem to bring nations close to Gellner’s account. But a public culture need not be comprehensive: indeed, it may not extend much beyond political principles and social norms (26), and may thus comprise a variety of private cultures. Three Observations. Three other brief observations about both kinds of nationalism are pertinent to what I will be saying later. First, national identity of both the civic and ethnic kind may be more or less important. This observation raises especially important issues about the argument from nation to state, but I willing not be considering that argument here. Second, both kinds of nationalism may be more or less determinate: thus the implications of the principles that define a civic nation may be uncertain (as Stanley Fish often points out), but the same is true of ethnically-defined national identities. Finally, third, though national identity is distinct from institutional membership, identities of both kinds may be created by institutions rather than antecedent to them.

2. States and Nations: Instrumental Argument Miller, I said, distinguishes two arguments in support of the nationality principle. The first argument is that nations are entitled to states because states enable members of nations to fulfill their obligations, help nations to preserve their

cultures, and enable nations to achieve collective self-determination. I will not be focusing here on this first line of argument. The second argument is that (what I will refer to for convenience as) the “successful conduct of politics” depends on a common national identity. More precisely, the provision of public goods, the achievement of distributive justice, and the operation of deliberative democracy all are promoted by national identity: that is, when the state coincides with a single nation, and is not multinational (though it may be multiethnic or multicultural). Call this the instrumental argument for the coincidence of state and nation: Beitz suggests it, when he says that the best case for national self-determination is that a correspondence of national and political boundaries may be an aid in the cause of justice.^1 And in his response to Nussbaum, Charles Taylor urges that achieving the justice embraced by cosmopolitans appears to require national attachments, because justice requires democracy and therefore some limits of equality. And both democracy and equality require “a high degree of mutual commitment[s]” to compatriots (Taylor in Nussbaum, 120). Cosmopolitan Nationalism. As the reference to Beitz indicates, and as Taylor suggests in his response to Nussbaum, this instrumental argument may be found attractive even by moral cosmopolitans, at least if we think of moral cosmopolitans as essentially being moral universalists, whose first principle is that the well-being of each person in the world matters equally. (Nussbaum’s cosmopolitanism seems ambiguous as between an endorsement of moral universalism and an endorsement of a personal ideal of thinking of one’s first (^1) For criticism, see Onora O’Neill, Bounds of Justice , pp. 179-181.

virtually self-evident that ties of community are an important source of such trust between individuals who are not personally known to one another and who are in no position directly to monitor one another’s behavior. A shared identity carries with it a shared loyalty, and this increases confidence that others will reciprocate one’s won cooperative behavior” (92). In the case of public goods, for example, people are more likely to do their share in supporting the provision of such goods, and in complying with rules designed to provide them (paying taxes, keeping the parks clean, getting rid of the SUV), if they have trust that others will do so as well. And they are more likely to go in for sincere and reasoned argument that deliberative democracy requires if they can trust others to do the same. I have four points to make about this argument.

  1. In explaining the link between national loyalty and political success Miller vacillates between emphasizing trust—confident expectations about the compliance of others—and emphasizing group solidarity—commitment to ensuring the success of others out of a sense of common group membership. The difference between trust and solidarity seems clear, as a matter of common sense: I trust Norwegians, but have no particular sense of solidarity with them: trust is epistemic, and concerns my beliefs about what others can be expected to do; solidarity is about motivations. The story about public goods is essentially about trust, whereas the story about distributive justice concerns solidarity (Miller shifts from “trust” to “solidarity” in a single paragraph [see 93] but seems not to notice the shift). The claim with respect to distributive justice is that the

willingness to forgo advantages that one could win in less regulated markets in order to ensure a decent life for others who do not succeed in the market depends on having a sense of being in community with those others: a sense of obligation to them as members of one’s own nation. The idea that distributive justice depends on a sense of solidarity and loyalty is an argument advanced by social democrats who are opposed to the European Union, precisely because they see it as undermining the national solidarities required for distributive justice. It is also the crux of Michael Sandel’s critique of Rawls: the idea that there is a tension between Rawls’s liberalism and his egalitarianism. Thus Rawlsian egalitarianism is said to require that we reject the idea of the priority of “plurality over unity,” and think of community allegiance as fundamental and constitutive, though—Sandel argues—such rejection stands in tension with the idea of antecedent individuation which is the basis of the liberal idea of the priority of individual rights. I will return to the issue of solidarity later. Suffice to say now that with this clarification, we have two basic ideas in play: first, that political success depends on trust and solidarity, and second that trust and solidarity depend on shared national identity.

  1. Before exploring those ideas, I make the second observation, which is that national solidarity, especially of the ethnic-nationalist kind, can be in deep tension with justice, democracy, and the broad provision of public goods, because ethnic nationalism is essentially exclusive: loyalty is to the group, and if the group is defined as essentially unjoinable (as in the traditional conception of

interested in political success for the European Union, we should not aim to promote a European political identity, but to encourage common projects that promise practical success. Second, while loyalties may help trust, they can make it hard to sustain trust because violations may be experienced as profound betrayals—betrayals of the group—and thus be very hard to repair: this could be a particularly severe problem for a highly determinate collective, national identity. Weaker ties may, on balance, make for more stable trust. Third, people can have reputations for being trustworthy even with those with whom they have no history of cooperation. Thus, I trust Norwegians and Swedes, for example. Even if the reputation for being trustworthy is founded in the first instance on an aspect of national identity, the reputation itself may extend to settings in which cooperation grows outside the circle of compatriots.

  1. Finally, it not clear why distributive justice depends on national solidarities: why a principled commitment to fairness will not do. Recall again the distinction between civic and ethnic nationalism. In the case of civic nationalism, the allegiance that binds the political society is to a set of principles. Suppose then that we can have a political society with a civic form of nationalism in which the content of the civic nationalism is given by principles of justice that require some form of egalitarian distribution. If that is possible, then suppose that we have a multinational state, and that each of the nations shares an allegiance to principles that require fair distribution of resources: the principles are different, and by all measures the groups do form different nations. Nevertheless, the

content of the loyalties that define them require them to ensure a relatively egalitarian distribution in the multinational society. So if an egalitarian civic nation is possible, it is not clear why an egalitarian multinational state is not possible. But, then, you might reject the antecedent. And the fact that Miller shifts, as I noted earlier, from trust to solidarity in the course of his discussion of distributive justice suggests that Miller might have trouble with the antecedent. That is, he might say (in effect with Sandel) that a political society will not embrace an egalitarian view of distributive justice unless it is founded on a richer, more substantial group bond than is characteristic of civic nationalism—not simply a unity founded on shared commitment to principles, but a unity that sustains the thought “ one of us should not be left to live that way.” You need group loyalty, not simply shared loyalty to principles. So thinner, civic nationalisms will all be more liberal and less egalitarian in content than ethno-cultural nationalisms. Even if, as Rawlsians suppose, a compelling argument is available within the framework of liberal principles for such an egalitarian view of justice, a more form civic form of nationalism will lack the motivational resources—the “high degree of mutual commitment”—required to sustain limits on inequality. Maybe this is right: because principles are motivationally weak, civic nationalism must be thin in content, and therefore multinational states are limited in the justice they can achieve. But two points about this: first, it would be worth considering whether there really is a correlation between forms of nationalism and content of views of justice on the dimension under consideration here (views