



Study with the several resources on Docsity
Earn points by helping other students or get them with a premium plan
Prepare for your exams
Study with the several resources on Docsity
Earn points to download
Earn points by helping other students or get them with a premium plan
Community
Ask the community for help and clear up your study doubts
Discover the best universities in your country according to Docsity users
Free resources
Download our free guides on studying techniques, anxiety management strategies, and thesis advice from Docsity tutors
This lecture handout is for Political Philosophy course. It was assigned by Prof. Jalendu Pillai at Bharathidasan University. It includes: Conception, Argument, Standards, Evaluating, Treatment, Political, Members, Global, Shared, Criticizing
Typology: Exercises
1 / 7
This page cannot be seen from the preview
Don't miss anything!
Comments on Human Rights
A conception of human rights is meant to play a certain role in global political argument (in what Rawls calls the “public reason of the society of peoples”): principles of human rights are meant to provide shared standards for evaluating and criticizing the practices of a political society in its treatment of its individual members. Three points—signaled by the three italicized phrases ( shared standards , practices of a political society , individual members )—are important in this characterization of human rights. First, the focus on individuals. The role of a conception of human rights is to present a set of important standards that all political societies are to be held accountable, by their members and by outsiders, in their treatment of individual members. A statement of human rights presents, as is commonly said, a set of limits on internal sovereignty, or—perhaps better—presents conditions on which a state’s internal sovereignty is acknowledged. The idea that there are such limits on internal sovereignty is often said to be a fundamental departure from the Westphalian conception of sovereignty that prevailed from the mid-17th^ century until the end of World War II. Krasner expresses some skepticism on this point: though the norms of Westphalian sovereignty deny external accountability, those norms, he argues, have persistently been violated by externally-guaranteed protections of rights; that’s why sovereignty is organized hypocrisy. The change since World War II,
Krasner claims, is better understood as a shift from abridgements in the name of minority group rights (always part of the Westphalian system) to abridgements in the name of individual human rights, rather than a shift in the basic understanding of sovereignty. Krasner is right to emphasize that protections of minority rights were abridgements of conventional understandings of internal sovereignty. But I suspect that the more recent developments have changed the norms of sovereignty themselves, and not simply shifted the content of the predictable abridgements of the conventional norms. Second, the conception of human rights is supposed, in some sense, to be shared : human rights standards are standards that can be endorsed by people who hold different religious and philosophical views. The standards represent a partial statement of the content of a global public reason: a public reason that is global in reach, inasmuch as it applies to all political societies, and global in its agent, inasmuch as it is presented as the common reason of all peoples, who share responsibility for interpreting its principles, and monitoring and enforcing them. Beitz suggests this point in his account of human rights as matters of common concern, and Ignatieff in his comments on how a conception of human rights should not be thought of as providing trumps that resolve disagreement, but as a “common framework, a common set of reference points that can assist parties in conflict to deliberate together” (20). This conception of shared framework was present from the outset in the evolution of the doctrine of human rights, as Glendon’s book on the Universal Declaration shows. Jacques Maritain—perhaps the central figure in mid-20th
tension: between a focus on individuals as the bearers of rights and on the importance of shared point of view. Before getting there, I want to mention the third point about human rights as global standards applied to organized political societies. Thus, if we think of natural rights as the rights that persons would have even in a non-institutional state of nature then human rights and natural rights are fundamentally different ideas. It might turn out to be true that human rights and natural rights are coextensive: that all that people can reasonably demand of an organized political society in its treatment of individuals is that the individuals have the protections that they would be entitled to even in a state of nature with no institutions. But it is not at all obvious that there are any such natural rights; if there are not, why anything follows about human rights; and if there are, why individual assurances in organized political societies should be confined to them. To see why consider the case of Bentham, who famously said that natural rights are nonsense and that natural and imprescriptible rights are nonsense on stilts. The point I want to make here is that these observations are entirely consistent with a Benthamite-utilitarian theory of human rights. And once we see that they are consistent, we will be less inclined to think that there is a tension between the first two elements of a conception of human rights—the fact that it is shared and the fact that it is focused on individual rights. Bentham had two reasons for disliking the idea of natural rights. First, he thought that the idea of natural rights (esp. imprescriptible natural rights) went along with the anti-legal-positivist thought that compatibility with natural rights is a
condition of legal validity (a legally valid regulation cannot deny natural rights), and the thought that we have no obligation to obey regulations that are not legally valid. So the idea of natural rights is destructive of political authority and stability: thus Bentham’s association of natural rights with anarchism. Moreover, Bentham thought—as a matter of analytical jurisprudence—that having a right requires a setting of organized political institutions. That ‘s because having a right requires that others have obligations, that obligations require laws, and that laws require a political authority who is habitually obeyed. So in the absence of a political authority there are no laws and therefore no rights. That’s why assertions about natural rights are nonsensical, and not simply false. But consistent with these points, a Benthamite utilitarian can also endorse a doctrine of human rights. Thus, the Benthamite says that human rights are the rights that all people ought to have , in any organized political society (either quite generally or at a certain historical period). The rights that people ought to have are the rights whose protection—via law (as Bentham and Habermas insist) and perhaps other systems of pressure and sanction (as Beitz suggests)—promotes the aggregate social welfare, understood by Bentham as the net balance of pleasure over pain. These are the rights whose protection is relatively inexpensive, and/or whose protection promises large benefits, and/or whose violation imposes large harms, and/or whose violation brings only small gains. So for example, there might be a human right to bodily integrity, violated by slavery, because the harms imposed on slaves by a system of slavery are greater than the benefits conferred on owners and third parties by that system. Or a human
duties: here, the rights are justified not by reference to their consequences for human welfare, as in utilitarianism, or by reference to the idea of a special moral status associated with capacity to choose, but are understood as enabling the proper fulfillment of those duties. Of course, more needs to be said on this point, about the nature of the duties, in order to explain why the fulfillment of duties might arguably require rights and not simply sanctions for failing to fulfill them. The point here is only to note that this idea of rights that enable the fulfillment of duties is available as a way to bring a conception of individual rights within a non- individualistic outlook, and thus to dampen the tension between the idea of human rights as a shared point of view and the idea of human rights as assigning rights to individuals.