






Study with the several resources on Docsity
Earn points by helping other students or get them with a premium plan
Prepare for your exams
Study with the several resources on Docsity
Earn points to download
Earn points by helping other students or get them with a premium plan
Community
Ask the community for help and clear up your study doubts
Discover the best universities in your country according to Docsity users
Free resources
Download our free guides on studying techniques, anxiety management strategies, and thesis advice from Docsity tutors
An historical account of why the European Convention on Human Rights was only recently incorporated into UK law. It discusses the British involvement in the drafting of the Convention, the country's decision to ratify it without submitting to the jurisdiction of the European Court or the individual petition right, and the introduction of the margin of appreciation principle. The text also touches upon the political pressure to avoid findings of Convention breaches and the eventual decision to incorporate the Convention into UK law.
Typology: Slides
1 / 10
This page cannot be seen from the preview
Don't miss anything!
The history of the Convention does not explain why it has only recently been incorporated into United Kingdom law. The significance of this is that under British Constitutional law, until a treaty has been incorporated into domestic law by an Act of Parliament it cannot be relied on directly in national courts by those who claim that it has been infringed by their government. As we have seen, in 1950 the United Kingdom was opposed to giving the European Court jurisdiction over complaints from British individuals. In addition, it was not thought particularly necessary to increase human rights protection in the United Kingdom, because it was thought at that time that the law of the United Kingdom adequately protected the rights of its citizens. Indeed, the British involvement in the drafting of the Convention supported the government’s view that the European Convention itself reflected the standards of protection provided by the tradition of English common law. Britain was, however, the first country to ratify the Convention, although it did not sign up to the optional provisions, namely, submission to the jurisdiction of the European Court and the right of individual petition, which allowed individuals to complain directly to the Commission or the Court. Britain also extended the effect of the Convention (but not the First Protocol) to most of its colonies on 23 October 1953, although during the following decades before most of the colonies gained their independence a number of derogations were entered in various emergency situations. Ironically, since it was largely responsible for the Convention coming into existence, Britain was also the subject of the first inter-state case to be brought under the Convention, which was a complaint to the Commission by Greece regarding the situation in Cyprus, brought in May 1956.^1 The complaint related to British actions taken and regulations imposed in response to the actions of the Greek-Cypriot group EOKA. Greece alleged that there had been breaches of a number of articles, especially Article 3 (freedom from torture) in relation to corporal punishment and treatment of detainees and Article 5 (prohibition of arbitrary detention). After a number of hearings and a visit to Cyprus by some of the Commission members in January 1958, the Commission reported in September 1958 into the regulations and systems in place in Cyprus.^2 The report found no
(^1) Application 176/1956. (^2) Greece brought a second application in July 1957, which raised 49 individual cases of alleged torture or mistreatment. This application was overtaken by events, because there was a settlement over Cyprus in February 1959 between Greece and Turkey, so none of the complaints proceeded to a hearing by the Commission.
human rights infringements by the United Kingdom, but did make some criticisms. Between the making of the complaint and the report being produced, some laws which might have infringed the Convention had also been repealed as a result of political pressure to avoid a finding by the Commission of a breach of human rights. The Commission report was notable for introducing into the Convention jurisprudence the idea of the margin of appreciation, which is the important principle that states have some leeway to deal with, in particular, emergency situations, before they breach the Convention.
The Cyprus cases did not encourage the British government to be enthusiastic to sign up to the optional provisions relating to the Court and the right of individual petition. The Colonial Office, which administered the various British territories, had always taken the view that the Convention might cause difficulties if there were too close an examination of the various legal systems in place in some of the colonies. In this view, signing up to a right of individual petition and the jurisdiction of the Court would only encourage complaints by agitators, especially those who wished to encourage the independence of the colony in question. In the early 1960s there were a number of formal derogations from the Convention in place in respect of various colonies, which is to say formal statements that the Convention was being disapplied in certain instances, precisely to cover various legislative provisions designed to allow systems of administration which might not conform to the requirements of the Convention but were thought necessary to deal with various situations.
However, during the early 1960s, Britain was dismantling its empire in a fairly comprehensive way, and by 1964 most of the larger colonies had been granted independence. There was also some political pressure for signing up to the optional clauses; the issue was raised with the government, in particular by Lord McNair, the first British judge on the European Court, and also the first President of the Court. There was a change of government in 1964 and the new Lord Chancellor, Lord Gardiner, supported signing up to the optional clauses. By late 1965 there were even fewer colonies -- the Colonial Office ceased to exist in 1966, replaced by the Commonwealth Office -- and in December 1965, the Prime Minister, Harold Wilson, announced that Britain would sign up to the optional clauses, which was done in January 1966.
At this stage there was no political pressure for the Convention to be directly incorporated into United Kingdom law. This was something which developed during the 1980s and 1990s, particularly after there had been a number of findings of infringements by the United Kingdom. These put paid to the view that United Kingdom law provided adequate human rights protection without the need for the Convention. However, the European Convention was not high on the political agenda, and it was only when it was made a matter of policy by the Labour Party, in opposition, in the mid-1990s that it gained any real political relevance.
judges or by Parliament. The Act specifically preserves the sovereignty of Parliament: it does not allow the courts to declare that any statute passed by Parliament is unlawful and so of no effect. Thus it does not change the constitutional relationship between Parliament and the courts or give the courts the powers that, for example, the Supreme Court of the Unites States has to declare legislation to be invalid if it is unconstitutional. The courts can only declare that the provisions of the statute are incompatible with the Act -- that is, one or more provisions of the statute in question infringe the human rights of some person or persons.
The Act therefore does not, in principle, infringe the sovereignty of Parliament -- it does not interfere with democratic process, or prevent a government being able to pursue the policies it was elected to pursue, not does it allow judges to overrule Parliament. This is important in principle. The justification for this limitation on the scope of the Act is that judges are not elected -- they are appointed on the basis of ability and experience -- and therefore they are not accountable to the general population. They cannot be elected out of office as politicians can be. It is quite appropriate, and indeed desirable, to have judges decide legal disputes, questions about what the law says in a particular area, or how the law should deal with a difficult case, since the resolution of such questions is based on expertise in the law. Considerations of general principles of morality and justice apply only in so far as there is any doubt as to what the law is or any question as to what the law should be, which only occurs in rare cases. Usually the dispute in a case being heard is about what the facts in dispute are, and how the law applies to those facts; it is rare for the facts to be clear but the law to be vague, and it is only in those situations that the judges may have to decide what the right answer should be.
However, questions of human rights may well involve political questions of the sort which should be decided as a matter of policy by Parliament. Members of Parliament are elected on the basis of their, or their party’s, political views on which policies should be adopted on a variety of important issues. They therefore have a democratic mandate to put forward certain views on contentious issues, and are accountable to the electorate for the way in which they present those views.
Thus questions such as how much money should be spent by the government in different areas such as defence or social security or whether the government should pursue a policy of building roads or railways to assist with transport are political, rather than legal. This is because these are questions on which there are a range of possible answers, where general principles of right and wrong do not lead to conclusions on the detail, and where the question is not what the law says (if anything), but what it ought to say. So, it may be a worthy general principle that we should all contribute to the funding of public transport, but that does not answer the political question as to how much money should be allocated to different areas.
In addition, political questions are not usually appropriate to the type of process used in judicial decision-making. This is because judges are there to decide the questions that relate to the dispute between the two parties before them: the right answer for that case on those facts. The sort of matters that we think of as political questions are typically ones where a more general approach is required, since there are invariably more than two different views on the right answer, and more than two parties or groups who will be affected by the solution chosen. There will also often be questions where getting to the best answer will involve much specialist or expert input. Courts have to rely on the expert evidence put before them by the parties to the dispute, whereas politicians and civil servants can be more proactive in seeking relevant information and have access to a wider variety of sources of information, not just those arguments put before them by the parties interested in any given issue.
There is, of course, often no clear distinction between legal and political questions and many questions will be one of degree. For example, where the law is not clear and there is a discretion to be exercised by the judges deciding a case, because their existing cases would support more than one answer, the judges may find themselves making a ‘political’ decision as to what the right answer should be. This will be especially so if the law is being challenged in the highest court, the House of Lords, where it may effectively be argued that the law should be changed: the Lords will then have to consider the more general implications of the decision they are making, and the policy which they would be implementing by taking a particular view. In such cases there may well be a difference of opinion precisely on whether such a decision should be made by the courts or by Parliament, and whether or not it is appropriate for the courts to be making that sort of decision.
An example of a situation where the courts expressly considered that a policy decision was being taken, and also an example of judicial review under the Act, is the case of Alconbury.^4 Here, what was being challenged was a ministerial decision under statutory powers to decide a question as to whether or not planning permission should be given for a number of proposed developments. What was being argued was that the Environment Secretary was not an independent and impartial tribunal within the meaning of Article 6(1) and therefore his power to decide these questions was incompatible with the Convention. The House of Lords rejected this argument. The role of the Secretary of State was quite appropriate since the decision at issue was one of administrative policy under the planning legislation. It would be undemocratic for the courts to determine planning questions themselves, since that was not the scheme of the legislation adopted by Parliament: the constitutional role of the Secretary of Sate was not a judicial role to which Article 6 applies, but involved a political, policy decision. However, overall Article 6 was complied with because the
(^4) R (Alconbury Developments Limited) v Secretary of State for the Environment, Transport and the Regions [2001] 2 WLR 1389.
and when and to what extent state interference is justified. In some areas there may be no general consensus across Europe about what should be tolerated and what should not, and what would suggest to the judges of the European Court that states should be given some scope for expressing the popular feelings of their citizens about a particular issue.
The European Court in this way accepts that different people may have different views on moral issues which are not necessarily ‘right’ or ‘wrong’. Another way of putting this is that it is based on the principle of subsidiarity, that matters should be decided at the most local level appropriate. The principle of a margin of appreciation recognizes that national courts may be best placed to make an initial assessment of the needs and standards of their own societies; or in some cases, that different countries have evolved different solutions to similar problems, especially on social and moral issues. But it should be emphasized that states will not be given a margin of appreciation on all issues, only where the European Court considers that there is a genuine difference of opinions across Europe and the right in question is one which permits different interpretations to be applied. There is no margin of appreciation to allow torture or slavery, for example, in breach of Articles 3 and 4. It is only on difficult moral issues that states may have a margin of appreciation.
One example is abortion: this is a difficult moral question on which people from different cultures and religions take different views. Under the Convention, the right to life contained in Article 2 is not qualified. However, different states have different laws about abortion. Some states prohibit abortion altogether, for example Ireland because of its predominantly Roman Catholic population; others, like the United Kingdom, allow abortion up to a certain stage of pregnancy. If the European Court was asked to consider whether abortion was an interference with the right to life or whether banning abortion was an interference with the rights of the mother, this is an area where an application of the margin of appreciation is likely, because there is no European consensus as to what is morally acceptable and what is not. This question has been considered by the European Commission, who have taken broadly this approach: they have taken the view that an unborn child does have some rights, but these are bound up with the rights of the mother.
The principle also reflects an important aspect of the function of the European Court. The European Court will only consider whether or not the judgments of the national courts, and the decisions of the national governments and officials, are in accordance with the principles of the Convention. If a judgment or decision causes a citizen to suffer a breach of his or her human rights, then the court will step in, by declaring that there has been a breach. But the European Court will not substitute its judgment for that of the national court on the application of national law, so it will not reach a decision as to whether or not the national law has been applied correctly. Nor will it review the admissibility or
relevance of the evidence adduced in the national court. It is in this sense a supervisory jurisdiction.
In the case of Handyside v UK,^5 the European Court was asked to consider the bringing of a prosecution in England for obscenity arising out of the publication of the Little Red Schoolbook, a book which was aimed at children and was prosecuted for its frank discussions of sexual matters. The publisher complained that his rights to freedom of expression under Article 10 had been infringed. The United Kingdom argued that any infringement was justified in the interest of the protection of morals. The European Court decided that, although the book had not been prosecuted in some other European countries where it had been published, it was within the margin of appreciation allowed to the United Kingdom authorities to consider that this book was unlawful in Britain. In particular, there was no uniform European conception of morals and on this ground of justification, state authorities were better placed than the European Court to give an opinion. The Court stated that the protection established by the Convention is in that sense subsidiary to the national system safeguarding human rights. The Court stressed, however, that allowing a margin of appreciation goes hand in hand with European overall supervision, in particular the limiting requirement of proportionality between the infringement of the right and its justification.
It should also be noted that the European Court has developed its ideas over time as the popular morality of Europe has changed. This is because the European Court treats the Convention as a developing instrument. This has affected what issues are considered to be ones where states have a margin of appreciation at any one time.
A recent example of the European Court developing the margin of appreciation is in the Court’s consideration of the rights of transsexuals, that is, people who undergo a sex-change operation. In the case of Goodwin v UK^6 the Court decided that there had been violations of Articles 8 (privacy) and 12 (right to marriage) in respect of two transsexuals. The Court recognized an international trend towards increased social acceptance of transsexuals and increased legal recognition of their new sexual identity, and came to the view that this could no longer be regarded as a matter of controversy. It was therefore no longer open to the United Kingdom to claim that their treatment of transsexuals fell within the margin of appreciation. This was particularly so given the lack of review which appeared to have been undertaken by the United Kingdom government since previous European Court decisions on the subject, notwithstanding changes in attitudes in society. The United Kingdom did however retain a margin of appreciation as to how the rights of transsexuals should be recognized and what changes to domestic law were required as a result.
(^5) (1979--80) 1 EHRR 737. (^6) Goodwin v UK (2002) 35 EHRR 18.
an offence was committed, infringes the Article 6 protection against self-incrimination and if so, whether any infringement is justified. The justification would be based on addressing the social problem of reducing traffic accidents, part of which involves ensuring that those responsible for accidents are prosecuted, which requires identification of the person driving the car. The Privy Council here held that there was no infringement of Article 6. One of the factors referred to by Lord Steyn was that Parliament was in as good a position as a court to assess the gravity of the problem and the public interest in addressing it, in requiring the identity of the driver to be disclosed. Again in a different context altogether: in the case of Popular Housing v Donoghue,^9 the court had to consider the statutory scheme for providing social housing. The Court Appeal considered that: The Court has to pay considerable attention to the fact that Parliament intended [.. .] to give preference to the needs of those dependent on social housing as a whole over those in the position of the defendant. The economic and other implications of any policy in this area are extremely complex and far-reaching. This is an area where, in our judgment, the courts must treat the decisions of Parliament as to what is in the public interest with particular deference. The limited role to the court [.. .] is a legislative policy decision. The correctness of this decision is more appropriate for Parliament than the courts and the Human Rights Act 1998 does not require the courts to disregard the decisions of Parliament in relation to situations of this sort when deciding whether there has been a breach of the Convention.
It is important that in complex areas, requiring political decisions as to the best of a range of permissible solutions, the courts do give weight to the decision of Parliament. However, it will also be important for the courts to ensure that they do not defer to Parliament too much. Deference to Parliament should not prevent the courts from intervening in situations where Parliament has gone beyond the boundaries of what is permitted by the Convention rights.
(^9) Popular Housing and Regeneration Community Association Ltd v Donoghue [2001].